World Scientific
  • Search
  •   
Skip main navigation

Cookies Notification

We use cookies on this site to enhance your user experience. By continuing to browse the site, you consent to the use of our cookies. Learn More
×

System Upgrade on Tue, May 28th, 2024 at 2am (EDT)

Existing users will be able to log into the site and access content. However, E-commerce and registration of new users may not be available for up to 12 hours.
For online purchase, please visit us again. Contact us at [email protected] for any enquiries.

New jump operators on equivalence relations

    https://doi.org/10.1142/S0219061322500155Cited by:2 (Source: Crossref)

    Abstract

    We introduce a new family of jump operators on Borel equivalence relations; specifically, for each countable group Γ we introduce the Γ-jump. We study the elementary properties of the Γ-jumps and compare them with other previously studied jump operators. One of our main results is to establish that for many groups Γ, the Γ-jump is proper in the sense that for any Borel equivalence relation E the Γ-jump of E is strictly higher than E in the Borel reducibility hierarchy. On the other hand, there are examples of groups Γ for which the Γ-jump is not proper. To establish properness, we produce an analysis of Borel equivalence relations induced by continuous actions of the automorphism group of what we denote the full Γ-tree, and relate these to iterates of the Γ-jump. We also produce several new examples of equivalence relations that arise from applying the Γ-jump to classically studied equivalence relations and derive generic ergodicity results related to these. We apply our results to show that the complexity of the isomorphism problem for countable scattered linear orders properly increases with the rank.

    1. Introduction

    The backdrop for our study is the Borel complexity theory of equivalence relations. Recall that if E,F are equivalence relations on standard Borel spaces X,Y then E is Borel reducible to F, written EBF, if there exists a Borel function f:XY such that

    xExf(x)Ff(x).
    We say f is a homomorphism if it satisfies the left-to-right implication. We write EBF if both EBF and FBE, and we write E<BF if both EBF and EBF.

    The notion of Borel reducibility gives rise to a preorder structure on equivalence relations. As with other complexity hierarchies, it is natural to study operations such as jumps.

    Definition 1.1. We say that a mapping EJ(E) on Borel equivalence relations is a proper jump operator if it satisfies the following properties for Borel equivalence relations E,F:

    Monotonicity: EBF implies J(E)BJ(F);

    Properness: E<BJ(E) whenever E has at least two equivalence classes.

    Note that the terms jump or jump operator may be used for a monotone mapping with EBJ(E) in a context where strict properness is not relevant or has not been established. We may also apply a jump operator to analytic equivalence relations; in this case we do not expect or require properness. Indeed, for all of the jump operators discussed below, one can find analytic equivalence relations which are fixed points for the mapping up to Borel bireducibility.

    One may also ask for some definability condition on a jump operator. While we do not require any particular such conditions, it is the case that all the jump operators discussed below are uniformly definable in the sense that if RY×X2 is a Borel set so that each section Ry is an equivalence relation on X, then the set R̃Y×X̃2 given by R̃(y,x̃1,x̃2) iff x̃1J(Ey)x̃2 is also Borel, where X̃ denotes the domain of J(E).

    Several jump operators have been studied extensively, including the Friedman–Stanley jump [13] and the Louveau jump [24], which we discuss below. There is also a jump operator on quasi-orders introduced by Rosendal [25]; see also subsequent work by Camerlo et al.[6].

    Here, we introduce a new class of jump operators which are associated with countable groups.

    Definition 1.2. Let E be an equivalence relation on X, and let Γ be a countable group. The Γ-jump of E is the equivalence relation E[Γ] defined on XΓ by

    xE[Γ]y(γΓ)(αΓ)x(γ1α)Ey(α).

    We will use the term Bernoulli jump as a collective name for any member of the family of Γ-jumps. Indeed, note that if E=Δ(2) then E[Γ] is the orbit equivalence relation induced by the classical Bernoulli shift action of Γ, and if E=Δ(X) for a Polish space X then E[Γ] is the orbit equivalence relation induced by the “generalized” Bernoulli action of Γ.

    We reserve the notation EΓ for the product of countably many copies of E with index set Γ. Thus EΓ is Borel isomorphic to Eω, and E[Γ] is an equivalence relation of countable index over EΓ. Indeed, letting Γ act on XΓ by the left shift γx(α)=x(γ1α), we have that x,y are E[Γ]-equivalent iff there is γΓ with γxEΓy.

    It is clear that the Γ-jump operator is monotone for any Γ. We will be concerned with whether and when the Γ-jump is proper. Before addressing this question, we recall the situation with the Friedman–Stanley and Louveau jumps.

    Definition 1.3. Let E be a Borel equivalence relation on X. The Friedman–Stanley jump of E is the equivalence relation E+ defined on Xω by

    xE+y{[x(n)]E:nω}={[y(n)]E:nω}.

    Theorem 1.1 ([13]). The mapping EE+ is a proper jump operator.

    Definition 1.4. Let E be a Borel equivalence relation on X and let be a free filter on ω. The Louveau jump of E with respect to is the equivalence relation E defined on Xω by

    xEy{nω:x(n)Ey(n)}.

    Theorem 1.2 ([24]). For any free filter , the mapping EE is a proper jump operator.

    The original proof of the Friedman–Stanley result used Friedman’s theorem on the non-existence of Borel diagonalizers (recall a Borel diagonalizer for E is a homomorphism φ from E+ to E so that φ(x){[xn]E:nω}). However, both the Friedman–Stanley result and the Louveau result can be proved using the concept of potential complexity of equivalence relations, which we briefly introduce. First, we will say that a Borel class is a pointclass Γ consisting of Borel sets and closed under continuous preimages. For example, Πα0 is a Borel class for any α<ω1.

    Definition 1.5. Let E be an equivalence relation on the Polish space (X,τ), and let Γ be a Borel class. We say E is potentially Γ, written Epot(Γ), if there is a topology σ on X such that σ,τ have the same Borel sets and such that E is in Γ with respect to σ.

    We remark that E is potentially Γ if and only if E is essentially Γ, i.e. there is some E in Γ with EBE.

    Definition 1.6. We say that a family 𝔉 of Borel equivalence relations has cofinal potential complexity if for every Borel class Γ there is E𝔉 such that Epot(Γ).

    Louveau established that if E is an equivalence relation with at least two classes, then the family of iterates of the Louveau jump of E with respect to a free filter has cofinal potential complexity. Since being potentially Γ is equivalent to being essentially Γ, a family of cofinal potential complexity cannot have a maximum element with respect to B. Hence it follows that the Louveau jump with respect to a free filter is a proper jump operator.

    Meanwhile it is known that the family of Borel equivalence relations induced by actions of S has cofinal potential complexity. Moreover, Hjorth–Kechris–Louveau [19] established that if E is an equivalence relation with at least two classes, then any Borel equivalence relation induced by an action of S is Borel reducible to some iterate of the Friedman–Stanley jump of E. Thus they arrived at a “potential complexity” proof that the Friedman–Stanley jump is a proper jump operator.

    Returning to the Bernoulli jumps, we will establish the following theorem.

    Theorem 1. Let Γ be a countable group so that  or p<ω for p prime is a quotient of a subgroup of Γ. Then the mapping EE[Γ] is a proper jump operator.

    In the proof, we will use a result of Solecki [28] which implies that if Γ is one of the groups or p<ω for p prime, then the family of Borel equivalence relations induced by actions of the group Γω has cofinal potential complexity. Our main work will be to show that such equivalence relations are Borel reducible to iterates of the Γ-jump. Before stating this result, we provide the following notation for the iterates of the Γ-jump.

    Definition 1.7. For an equivalence relation E and a countable group Γ we define the iterates Jα[Γ](E) of the Γ-jump recursively by

    J0[Γ](E)=E,Jα+1[Γ](E)=(Jα[Γ](E))[Γ],Jλ[Γ](E)=α<λJα[Γ](E)[Γ]forλalimit.
    We use Jα[Γ] to denote Jα[Γ](Δ(2)) and Zα to denote Jα[](Δ(2)).

    The tower of Zα is of particular interest and will figure in an application to the classification of scattered linear orders. We note that Δ(2) may be replaced by any nontrivial Polish space to produce equivalent iterates for α1. Also, in the definition of Jα[Γ](E), the third rule may be used for successor ordinals as well.

    Returning to the proof of Theorem 1, we will actually consider a more complicated group than Γω. For a countable group Γ, we will introduce the notion of a Γ-tree, which is a tree in which the children of each node carry the structure of a subset of the group Γ. We will see that Γ-trees are closely tied to iterates of the Γ-jump in a way analogous to the way regular trees are tied to iterates of the Friedman–Stanley jump. Namely, the iterated Γ-jump Jα[Γ] will be Borel bireducible with the isomorphism relation on well-founded Γ-trees of rank 1+α.

    In particular, we will introduce the full Γ-tree TΓ, which may be naturally identified with Γ<ω. Its automorphism group, Aut(TΓ), is a closed subgroup of S, and the group Γω is a closed subgroup of Aut(TΓ). We will establish the following theorem.

    Theorem 2. Let Γ be a countable group. Then for any Borel equivalence relation E such that E is induced by a Borel action of a closed subgroup of Aut(TΓ), there exists α such that E is Borel reducible to Jα[Γ].

    Since this result applies to the group Γω, when it is combined with the result of Solecki showing such groups have non-Borel orbit equivalence relations, it is sufficient to prove Theorem 1.

    The Bernoulli jumps are not always proper jump operators. In particular, we will establish the following theorem.

    Theorem 3. Let Γ be a countable group with no infinite sequence of strictly descending subgroups. Then the mapping EE[Γ] is not a proper jump operator.

    To establish this result, we directly calculate that for such Γ, we have that Jω+1[Γ] is Borel bireducible with Jω[Γ].

    Theorems 1 and 3 leave open the question of precisely when the Γ-jump is proper. Indeed, we shall see that there exist groups Γ which do not meet the hypothesis of either result.

    We will also study the structure of specific Borel equivalence relations with respect to the Bernoulli jumps and see that they provide new examples of equivalence relations whose complexity lies between E and F2. We first establish:

    Theorem 4. E0[Γ] is generically Eω-ergodic.

    This result has subsequently been strengthened by Allison and Panagiotopoulos [2] to show that E0[] is generically ergodic with respect to any orbit equivalence relation of a TSI Polish group. Using this, we establish:

    Theorem 5. We have the following:

    E0ω<BE0[]<BE[]<BF2.

    E0ω<BEω<BE[]<BF2.

    E0[] and Eω are B-incomparable.

    Shani [26] has produced further non-reducibility results about Bernoulli jumps of countable Borel equivalence relations. For instance, he has shown that E0[]<BE0[2], and that E0[] and E0[2<ω] are B-incomparable. He has also produced another example of an equivalence relation strictly between Eω and F2 which is B-incomparable with E0[] and E[].

    One application of the theory of Bernoulli jumps is to the classification of countable scattered linear orders. Recall that a linear order is scattered if it has no subordering isomorphic to (,<). The class of scattered linear orders carries a derivative operation where one identifies points x,y such that the interval [x,y] is finite. This derivative operation may furthermore be used to define a rank function on the countable scattered orders with values in ω1, as we will discuss in Sec. 9. We will establish the following theorem.

    Theorem 6. The isomorphism equivalence relation on countable scattered linear orders of rank 1+α is Borel bireducible with Jα[].

    This result, together with the fact that the -jump is proper, implies that the complexity of the classification of countable scattered linear orders increases strictly with the rank.

    This paper is organized as follows. In Sec. 2, we establish some of the basic properties of the Γ-jump. In Sec. 3, we compare the Γ-jump with the Friedman–Stanley jump. In Sec. 4, we introduce Γ-trees and relate iterates of the Γ-jump to isomorphism of well-founded Γ-trees. In Sec. 5, we study actions of Aut(TΓ) and prove Theorem 2. In Sec. 6, we investigate the properness of the Γ-jump and in particular prove Theorems 1 and 3. In Sec. 7, we revisit the proof from Sec. 5 and show that in some cases, we can achieve better lower bounds on the complexity of the iterated jumps. In Sec. 8, we investigate new equivalence relations arising from Bernoulli jumps, and compare them against well-known equivalence relations, establishing Theorems 4 and 5. In Sec. 9, we discuss the connection between the -jump and scattered linear orders, and in particular prove Theorem 6.

    2. Properties of the Γ-Jump for a Countable Group Γ

    In this section, we explore some of the basic properties of the Γ-jump. We begin by recording the following three properties, whose proofs are immediate.

    Proposition 2.1. For any countable group Γ and equivalence relations E and F, we have

    (a)

    If E is Borel (respectively, analytic), then E[Γ] is Borel (respectively, analytic).

    (b)

    EBE[Γ].

    (c)

    If EBF then E[Γ]BF[Γ].

    The next result strengthens Proposition 2.1(b).

    Proposition 2.2. If E is a Borel equivalence relation and Γ is an infinite group, then EωBE[Γ].

    Proof. If E has just finitely many classes, the left-hand side is smooth. Otherwise for any aX, we have that E is Borel bireducible with EX\[a]. Hence, it is sufficient to define a reduction from (EX\[a])ω to E[Γ].

    Let SΓ be an infinite subset such that γ1 implies γSS. (The set of such S is of measure 1.) Define a function f:(X\[a])SXΓ by

    f(x)(α)=x(α),ifαS,a,otherwise.
    Clearly, if xESx then f(x)EΓf(x) and therefore f(x)E[Γ]f(x). For the reverse implication suppose f(x)E[Γ]f(x), and let γΓ be such that γf(x)EΓf(x). Then f(x)(γα)Ef(x)(α), so
    f(x)(α)=af(x)(γα)=a.
    This means precisely that γS=S. It follows that γ=1, and therefore that xESx. □

    The Γ-jump may be thought of as a kind of wreath product. Recall that if Λ,Γ are groups then the full support wreath product ΛΓ is defined as follows. Let ΛΓ be the full support group product of Γ many copies of Λ, and let Γ act on ΛΓ by the shift. Then ΛΓ is the semidirect product ΓΛΓ with respect to this action.

    Proposition 2.3. If EΛ is the orbit equivalence relation of some (possibly uncountable) group Λ acting on X, and Γ is any countable group, then (EΛ)[Γ] is the orbit equivalence relation of ΛΓ acting on XΓ.

    This result implies that the Γ-jump preserves many properties of orbit equivalence relations. For the next statement, recall that a cli group is one which carries a complete, left-invariant metric.

    Corollary 2.1. If E is the orbit equivalence relation of a Polish group then E[Γ] is the orbit equivalence relation of a Polish group. The same statement holds if we replace “Polish group” with any of the following: solvable group, cli group, or closed subgroup of S.

    This follows for cli groups from the preservation of being a cli group under wreath products [14, Theorem 2.2.11]. Note, however, that being induced by a TSI group is not preserved (here a TSI group is one which carries a two-sided invariant metric). Indeed, it is shown in [2] that E0[] cannot be the orbit equivalence relation of a TSI group.

    By contrast, the Louveau jump does not satisfy any of these preservation properties. For example, the Louveau jump of Δ() with respect to the Fréchet filter is E1, and it is well-known E1 is not reducible to a Polish group action [15]. The Friedman–Stanley jump does satisfy the above preservation property with respect to Polish groups and subgroups of S. However, it does not satisfy the above preservation property with respect to solvable groups, TSI groups, or cli groups. For example, the Friedman–Stanley jump of Δ() is F2 and it is well-known F2 is not induced by a cli group action [21].

    Proposition 2.4. Let E be an equivalence relation on X. If Λ is a subgroup or quotient of Γ, then E[Λ]BE[Γ].

    Proof. We adapt the argument from the case when E is an equality relation (see [14, Proposition 7.3.4]). If Λ is a quotient of Γ, let π:ΓΛ be a surjective homomorphism and define f:XΛXΓ by f(x)=xπ. Then whenever λ=π(γ) we have

    λxEΛx(αΛ)x(λ1α)Ex(α)(βΓ)x(π(γ1β))Ex(π(β))(βΓ)f(x)(γ1β)Ef(x)(β)γf(x)EΓf(x).
    It follows that f is a reduction from E[Λ] to E[Γ].

    Next, assume that ΛΓ. Fix an element aX, and let f:XΛXΓ be defined by

    f(x)(α)=x(α),αΛ,a,otherwise.
    Clearly if λxEΛx then λf(x)EΓf(x) as well, which means xE[Λ]x implies f(x)E[Γ]f(x). For the reverse implication, suppose f(x)E[Γ]f(x), and let γΓ be such that γf(x)EΓf(x). If γ=λΛ, it is clear that λxEΛf(x) and so xE[Λ]x. On the other hand if γΛ, then for all λΛ, we have
    x(λ)=f(x)(λ)Eγf(x)(λ)=f(x)(γ1λ)=a.
    An identical calculation with x,x exchanged and γ,γ1 exchanged shows the same for x. Thus, in this case xEΛx and hence we have xE[Λ]x, as desired. □

    Next, we can relate jumps for finite powers of a group Γ to iterates of the jump for Γ.

    Lemma 2.1. For any countable group Γ, we have E[Γk]BJk[Γ](EΓk). In particular, E[Γk]BJk+1[Γ](E).

    Proof. Beginning with the first statement, we show the case of k=2, with larger k being similar. Given xXΓ×Γ let fx be the function from Γ×Γ to XΓ×Γ so that fx(α,β) is a code for all of the x(γ,δ), viewed from the base point (α,β), i.e., fx(α,β)(γ,δ)=x(αγ,βδ). We now define a reduction φ from E[Γ2] to ((EΓ2)[Γ])[Γ] by setting φ(x)(α)(β)=fx(α,β)

    If x is equivalent to y, witnessed by (α,β), then φ(x) is equivalent to φ(y) with the witness α for the outer jump and β for each coordinate of the inner jump. Conversely if φ(x) is equivalent to φ(y), then there exists (α,β) such that fx(1,1) is equivalent to fy(α,β). It follows that (α,β) witnesses that x is equivalent to y.

    The second statement follows from Proposition 2.2. □

    We can also absorb countable powers in certain Γ-jumps.

    Proposition 2.5. If E is a Borel equivalence relation and Γ and Δ are infinite groups, then (Eω)[Γ]BE[Γ×Δ].

    Proof. Arguing as in Proposition 2.2, we may assume E has infinitely many classes, and find a reduction from ((EX\[a])ω)[Γ] to E[Γ×Δ] for some aX. Let Δ={δn:nω}. For x((X\[a])ω)Γ, define f(x) by

    f(x)((α,δn))=x(α)(n1),ifn>1,a,ifn=0.
    If x(Eω)[Γ]x then f(x)E[Γ×Δ]f(x). Conversely, suppose f(x)E[Γ×Δ]f(x) and let (γ,δ) be such that (γ,δ)f(x)EΓ×Δf(x). Then we must have δ=1Δ, so that γx(Eω)[Γ]x and hence x(Eω)[Γ]x. □

    In particular, if Γ has a subgroup isomorphic to Γ×Δ for some infinite group Δ, then (Eω)[Γ]BE[Γ].

    Another property of equivalence relations is that of being pinned, which is defined using forcing. We briefly recall the definition; we refer the reader to [21] or [30] for properties of pinned equivalence relations.

    Definition 2.1. Let E be an analytic equivalence relation on X. A virtual E-class is a pair ,τ where is a poset and τ is a -name so that ×τEτr, where τ and τr are the interpretations of τ using the left and right generics, respectively. A virtual E-class ,τ is pinned if there is some xX from the ground model so that τEx̌. We say that E is pinned if every virtual E-class is pinned.

    Theorem 2.1. If E is pinned then E[Γ] is pinned.

    Proof. Suppose E is pinned and let ,τ be a virtual E[Γ]-class. Then ×τE[Γ]τr. Hence (γ)(λ)τ(λ)Eτr(γλ). We can therefore find a condition (p,q) and a γΓ such that

    (p,q)(λ)τ(λ)Eτr(γ̌λ).
    Then temporarily considering the forcing 3 and the three factor terms τ0,τ1,τ2, we have:
    (p,q,p)(λ)τ0(λ)Eτ1(γ̌λ)Eτ2(λ).
    Since E is transitive this implies that
    (p,p)(λ)τ(λ)Eτr(λ).

    Now, since E is pinned we can find xXΓ such that for all λ we have pτ(λ)Ex̌(λ). It follows that pτE[Γ]x̌. Finally, we claim this is in fact unconditionally forced. Indeed, if q is any other condition then (p,q)τE[Γ]x̌τE[Γ]τr. Again using the transitivity of E, we conclude that qτE[Γ]x̌ too. □

    By contrast, the Friedman–Stanley jump does not preserve pinned-ness, as the relation Δ()+BF2 is not pinned (see [21, 17.1.3]). Kanovei also shows in [21] that pinned-ness is preserved under Fubini products, so that the Louveau jump with the respect to the Fréchet filter does preserve pinned-ness.

    Remark 2.1. We feel that Corollary 2.1 and Theorem 2.1 justify the following Proclamation: The Γ-jump is a kinder, gentler jump operator than the Louveau jump or the Friedman–Stanley jump.

    We may view the Friedman–Stanley jump and the Γ-jumps as special cases of a more general construction. Let E be an equivalence relation on X, and let (G,A) be a permutation group of a countable set A. We define the jump E[G,A] on XA by

    xE[G,A]x(gG)(aA)x(g(a))Ex(a).
    The permutation group S=(Aut(),) corresponds to the Friedman–Stanley jump. In general the (G,A)-jump of a Borel equivalence relation need not be Borel; for example if E has at least two equivalence classes, then the (Aut(),)-jump of E is Borel complete. To see this, observe that we can reduce isomorphism of countable linear orders by embedding a countable linear order as a suborder of in X using two distinct E-classes, and isomorphism of countable linear orders is Borel-complete by [13, Theorem 3]. One may ask which (uncountable) group actions on give rise to various types of equivalence relations, e.g. Borel complete relations, Borel equivalence relations, or the Friedman–Stanley jump. In [2], the authors investigate this generalization, studying a P-jump operator for a Polish group P of permutations of .

    We may also ask how Γ-jumps for different groups Γ compare to one another.

    Question 2.1. Given a fixed E, how many distinct complexities can arise as E[Γ]? For countable groups Γ1 and Γ2, when is E[Γ1]BE[Γ2]?

    Here, Shani [26] has characterized strong ergodicity between Γ-jumps of countable Borel equivalence relations in terms of group-theoretic properties, showing in particular:

    Theorem 2.2 ([26, Corollary 1.4]). Let E be a generically ergodic countable Borel equivalence relation. Then:

    E[]<BE[2]<BE[3]<B<BE[<ω]<BE[𝔽2];

    E[] and E[2<ω] are B-incomparable.

    This contrasts sharply with the case of group actions, where actions of any two infinite countable abelian groups produce hyperfinite equivalence relations. It also shows that there is no “least” Γ-jump, although the 𝔽2-jump is the most complicated. We do not know whether incomparability can be extended to iterated jumps, such as through some notion of rigidity. Note, for instance, that by Lemma 2.1 we have E[2]BJ3[](E).

    Question 2.2. Are there countable groups Γ1 and Γ2 so that Jα[Γ1](E) and Jβ[Γ2](E) are B-incomparable for all α,β>0?

    We also introduce two restrictions of Bernoulli jumps.

    Definition 2.2. Let E be an equivalence relation on X and Γ a countable group. The free part of XΓ and the pairwise-inequivalent part of XΓ are given by

    XfreeΓ={x̄XΓ:γ(γ1Γγx̄Γx̄)},Xp.i.Γ={x̄XΓ:γ,δ(γδx̄(γ)x̄(δ))}.
    We let Efree[Γ]=EΓXfreeΓ and Ep.i.[Γ]=EΓXp.i.Γ.

    We immediately have Ep.i.[Γ]BEfree[Γ]BE[Γ]. We will see below that in certain cases all three are bireducible, but this is not true in general. Indeed, this fails already for E=Δ(2), as Δ(2)[𝔽2] is the shift equivalence relation E(𝔽2,2) which is bireducible with the universal countable Borel equivalence relation E by [11, Proposition 1.8], whereas Δ(2)free[𝔽2] is the free part of the shift, which is bireducible with the universal treeable countable Borel equivalence relation ET and hence strictly below (see, e.g. [20, Theorem 3.17 and Corollary 3.28]).

    Question 2.3. For which E and Γ do we have E[Γ]BEfree[Γ] or Efree[Γ]BEp.i.[Γ]?

    3. Comparing Γ-Jumps to Friedman–Stanley Jumps

    We begin by recalling that the Friedman–Stanley tower Fα for α<ω1 is defined analogously to the iterated Γ-jump.

    Definition 3.1. The equivalence relation Fα for α<ω1 is defined recursively by

    F0=Δ(ω),Fα+1=Fα+,Fλ=α<λFα+forλa limit.
    Equivalently, Fα is the isomorphism relation on countable well-founded trees on ω of height at most 1+α.

    We compare the -jump to the Friedman–Stanley jump.

    Definition 3.2. We say that E is weakly absorbing if E has perfectly many classes and (E<ω)+BE+.

    Note that if E has perfectly many classes and E×EBE, then E is weakly absorbing, so in particular this holds for E0, E, and Fα for all α1.

    Lemma 3.1. For any E with at least two classes, E[] is weakly absorbing.

    Proof. When E has at least two classes, E[] is above E0 and hence has perfectly many classes. We define a reduction from ((E[])<ω)+ to (E[])+ as follows. Fix E-inequivalent points z0 and z1. Given {(xm,0,,xm,km):mω}, let it map to the set {yi1,,ikmm:mω,i1,,ikm}, where

    yi1,,ikmm=,z0,z1,x0m,0,x0m,0,xi1m,1,xi1m,1,,xikmm,km,xikmm,km,z0,z1,x1m,0,x1m,0,x1+i1m,1,x1+i1m,1,,x1+ikmm,km,x1+ikmm,km,z0,z1,,
    i.e. yi1,,ikmm consists of a -sequence of blocks, indexed by k, of the form xkm,0,xkm,0,xk+i1m,1,xk+i1m,1,,xk+ikmm,km,xk+ikmm,km, separated by the pair z0, z1. If
    (xm,0,,xm,km)(E[])<ω(x̃m̃,0,,x̃m̃,k̃m̃)
    then km=k̃m̃ and there are j0,,jkm so that
    xjm,0Ex̃j+j0m̃,0xjm,1Ex̃j+j1m̃,1xjm,kmEx̃j+jkmm̃,km
    for all j, and hence yi1,,ikmmE[]i1+j1j0,,ikm+jkmj0m̃. Thus, the function defined is a homomorphism. Conversely, because of the repetition in the blocks, we can recover the (E[])<ω-class of (xm,0,,xm,km) from any yi1,,ikmm, so that it is also a cohomomorphism and hence a reduction. □

    Lemma 3.2. If E has perfectly many classes then Efree[]B(E<ω)p.i.[].

    Proof. Given a non-periodic -sequence x of E-representatives, we construct a new sequence y as follows. For each n we first define a real pn by pn(k,l)=1 iff xn+kExn+l. We then let dn be the least d>0 such that xnExn+d and pn=pn+d, if such exists, and dn=0 otherwise. Finally, we let yn=(pn,xn,,xn+dn). Thus, each coordinate yn has several pieces, and we say that two such coordinates yn and yn are equivalent if they are equivalent with respect to Δ()×E<ω.

    We claim that the entries yn are pairwise inequivalent. If this is not the case, we can find n0<n1 such that yn0 is equivalent to yn1. Let d=dn0=dn1. Note that d>0. Then the blocks xn0,,xn0+d and xn1,,xn1+d are pointwise E-equivalent. Next, since we have xn0+iExn1+i for id, and since pn0+d=pn0, we can conclude xn0+d+iExn1+d+i. Using this reasoning inductively, we can conclude that xn0+kd+iExn1+kd+i for all k>0. The fact that pn0+d=pn0 can be used right-to-left to obtain the same for k negative as well. In other words, x is periodic with period n1n0. This contradicts our assumption, and completes the claim.

    Thus the map xy is a reduction from the free part of E[] to the pairwise inequivalent part of (Δ()×E<ω)[]. Since E has perfectly many classes we have Δ()×E<ωBE<ω, so Efree[]B(E<ω)p.i.[]. □

    Theorem 3.1. If E is weakly absorbing then E[]BE+.

    Proof. Since E has perfectly many classes, we may fix a,bX with ab so that EBEX\[{a,b}]. From the previous lemma we then have that there is a reduction g from Efree[] to ((EX\[{a,b}])<ω)p.i.[]. Let P=k1Pk be the set of periodic elements, where Pk consists of xX such that for all n we have xnExn+k. Let k(x) be the least k1 so that xPk if xP, and k(x)=0 if xP. We now define a reduction f from E[] to (E<ω)+ as follows; since E is weakly absorbing this will be sufficient. If k(x)>0, we let f map xPk(x) to {(a,xi,xi+1,,xi+k(x)1):0i<k(x)}. If k(x)=0, let f map x to {g(x)nbg(x)n+1:n}, noting that the concatenation map (z,w)zbw provides a reduction from ((EX\[{a,b}])<ω)2 to E<ω.

    Suppose first that xE[]x. If xP then xP and k(x)=k(x), so that

    {[(a,xi,xi+1,,xi+k(x)1)]E<ω:0i<k(x)}={[(a,xi,xi+1,,xi+k(x)1)]E<ω:0i<k(x)}.
    If x,xP, then there is m with g(x)nE<ωg(x)m+n for all n. Then
    {[g(x)n,b,g(x)n+1]E<ω:n}={[g(x)m+n,b,g(x)m+n+1]E<ω:n}={[g(x)n,b,g(x)n+1]E<ω:n},
    i.e. f(x)(E<ω)+f(x).

    Suppose conversely that f(x)(E<ω)+f(x). We must have either both x,xP or both x,xP. If x,xP then we must have k(x)=k(x), and there are i and i so that xi+jExi+j for 0j<k(x), and hence xi+jExi+j for all j, so xE[]x. Suppose then x,xP. Then {[g(x)n,b,g(x)n+1]E<ω:n}={[g(x)n,b,g(x)n+1]E<ω:n}, so for each n there is an m(n) with g(x)nE<ωg(x)m(n) and g(x)n+1E<ωg(x)m(n)+1. Because the g(x)m’s are pairwise inequivalent, we conclude that m(n+1)=m(n)+1 for all n, so there is m with m(n)=n+m for all n. Thus, g(x)(E<ω)[]g(x) so xE[]x. □

    It turns out that E[Γ] is not reducible to E+ in general. In particular the following is shown in [3]:

    Theorem 3.2 (Shani). (E0ω)[] is not potentially Π30. Hence, neither (E0ω)[] nor (E0)[2] is reducible to F2.

    Noting that (E0)+BF2, we thus have that (E0)[2]B(E0)+.

    Question 3.1. For which E and Γ is E[Γ]BE+?

    A slight modification of the argument in 3.1 can be used to show:

    Lemma 3.3. (E0)[]B(E0)p.i.[], i.e. Z2 is Borel reducible to the pairwise inequivalent part of Z2.

    Proof. Note that E0<ω is hyperfinite, as is any equivalence relation of finite index over E0<ω, and hence reducible to E0. Thus, using Lemma 3.2, we may fix pairwise E0-inequivalent {an:n} and find a reduction f from (E0)free[] to (E0X\A)p.i.[], where A=n[an]. We extend f to the periodic part of (E0)[] as follows. With the notation from above, for xP let

    g(x)={(xi,xi+1,,xi+k(x)1):0i<k(x)}.
    The relation that such finite sets consist of the same E0<ω-classes is then hyperfinite, being of finite index over E0<ω, so we may fix a reduction h of (E0)[]P to E0X\A. Then for xP we let f(x)(0)=h(x) and f(x)(n)=an for n0 to complete the definition of f. □

    The same technique can be applied to the -jump of some other equivalence relations, such as E and F2, but we do not know if this is true for other E.

    We can now compare the hierarchy Zα with the hierarchy Fα.

    Theorem 3.3. For all α2, Zα is Borel reducible to Fα.

    Proof. By induction on α. The case of α=2 follows from Theorem 3.1 since Z2BE0[] and F2BE0+, and each iteration of the -jump preserves the property of being weakly absorbing so we may again apply Theorem 3.1. □

    As noted earlier, Γ-jumps are gentler than the Friedman–Stanley jump so the reverse of Theorem 3.3 is false.

    Proposition 3.1. F2 is not Borel reducible to Jα[Γ] for any α<ω1.

    Proof. Jα[Γ] is pinned because the identity relation is pinned, and Γ-jumps and countable products of pinned relations are pinned. On the other hand, F2 is not pinned and being pinned is preserved downward under B. □

    As E0+BE+BF2, we get the following corollary.

    Corollary 3.1. E0[]<BF2 and E[]<BF2.

    Although none of the Zα’s are above F2, we will see below that they are unbounded in Borel complexity.

    The result of Shani noted above shows that Theorem 3.3 does not hold for all countable groups Γ, as we do not always have J2[Γ]BF2, e.g. for Γ=2 (since J1[2]BE0). Proposition 7.1 will show that this also does not hold for Γ=2<ω. Potential complexity bounds do allow us to give a weaker comparison, which Proposition 7.1 will show to be the best possible in general.

    We refer below to the equivalence relations α*, which are defined in [19, Sec. 6]. These may be viewed as restricted forms of the relations Fα; we do not need the specifics of their definitions, but note the key point that α*<BFα for all α for which they are defined. We also recall that for a pointclass Γ, the pointclass D(Γ) consists of all sets which are the difference of two sets in Γ.

    Lemma 3.4. Fα[Γ]Bα+1* for α2, and hence Fα[Γ]<BFα+1 for α>0.

    Proof. Theorem 2 of [19] shows that for a Borel equivalence relation E induced by an action of a closed subgroup of S we have EFα iff Epot(Πα+10) for α>0 not a limit, and EFα iff Epot(Πα0) for α a limit. Then Fα[Γ] is still induced by an action of a closed subgroup of S and is in pot(Σα+20) for α not a limit or in pot(Σα+10) for α a limit. From [19, Theorem 4.1] we then have that Fα[Γ]pot(D(Πα+10)) for α not a limit, and hence by [19, Corollary 6.4] we have Fα[Γ]Bα+1*<BFα+1 in both cases for α2. The case of α=1 is immediate since F1[Γ] is countable and hence strictly below F2. □

    From this we conclude the following proposition.

    Proposition 3.2. For any countable group Γ and α2 we have Jα[Γ]Bα+1*, so for any α<ω1 we have Jα[Γ]<BFα+1.

    Proof. Note that J0[Γ]=Δ(2)<BΔ()=F1 and J1[Γ]<BF2 since it is countable. We proceed by induction on α. Successor steps follow immediately from the previous lemma. For a limit ordinal λ, if Jα[Γ]<BFα+1 for all α<λ, then

    Jλ[Γ]=α<λJα[Γ][Γ]Bα<λFα+1[Γ]BFλ[Γ]Bλ+1*
    by the previous lemma. □

    From [19, Corollary 6.4] we then have the following corollary.

    Corollary 3.2. For any countable group Γ we have J0[Γ]Δ10, J1[Γ]Σ20, and:

    Jα[Γ]pot(D(Πα+10)) for α2 not a limit;

    Jλ[Γ]pot(Σλ+10) for λ a limit.

    4. Γ-Trees

    The Friedman–Stanley jump naturally corresponds to the group S and its iterates correspond to isomorphism of well-founded trees. Namely, the equivalence relation Fα is bireducible with the isomorphism relation on countable well-founded trees of rank at most 2+α. We will see that Γ-jumps naturally correspond to certain group actions, and the iterates Jα[Γ] correspond to isomorphism of well-founded Γ-trees, which are trees where the children of each node carry the structure of a subset of Γ. We make this precise as follows.

    Definition 4.1. Let Γ be a countable group. The language Γ consists of the binary relation together with binary relations {Rγ:γΓ}. A Γ-tree is an Γ-structure which is a rooted tree with child relation and satisfies the additional (Γ)ω1ω-formulas:

    Rγ(u,v)t(utvt), for each γΓ with γ1Γ

    R1Γ(u,v)u=v

    t(utvt)γΓRγ(u,v)

    ¬(Rγ(u,v)Rδ(u,v)), for each γδΓ

    (Rγ(u,v)Rδ(v,w))Rγδ(u,w), for each γ,δΓ.

    We say that a Γ-tree is well-founded if it is well-founded as a tree, and we define rank in the usual way. Note that our definition ensures all Γ-trees are countable. Next, we introduce the full Γ-tree, TΓ. The automorphism group of TΓ will figure crucially in the following section.

    Definition 4.2. Let Γ be a countable group. The full Γ-tree, denoted TΓ, is the non-empty Γ-tree which additionally satisfies (t)(u)(ut), and for each γΓ:

    (t)(ut)(vt)Rγ(u,v).

    This produces a categorical theory and defines the full Γ-tree uniquely up to isomorphism. For one model of TΓ, we take the universe to be Γ<ω and interpret each Rγ by Rγ(sα,sβ)αγ=β.

    Definition 4.3. We let Γ denote the isomorphism relation on Γ-trees. For α<ω1 we let αΓ denote the isomorphism relation on well-founded Γ-trees of rank at most 1+α.

    Since every Γ-tree is isomorphic to a substructure of the full Γ-tree TΓ, we have that Γ is induced by an action of its automorphism group, Aut(TΓ). This group is isomorphic to the infinite wreath power Γω, a cli group, and hence Γ and any other Aut(TΓ)-action is pinned.

    We now can relate iterated Γ-jumps to isomorphism of well-founded Γ-trees. Nodes of rank 1 in a Γ-tree carry more structure than in a regular tree, where there are only countably many isomorphism types; hence the indexing differs by 1 from the case of the Fα and tree isomorphism. Also note that J0[Γ] is Δ(2), whereas 0Γ is Δ(1).

    Proposition 4.1. For each 0<α<ω1, Jα[Γ] is Borel bireducible with αΓ.

    Proof. For α=1, J1[Γ] is the shift of Γ on 2Γ, E(Γ,2). Given an element x2Γ we naturally associate a Γ-tree T(x) of rank 2 consisting of a root v with children {uα:x(α)=1}, where we interpret Rγ(uα,uβ)αγ=β. If xE(Γ,2)x, with γ0x=x, then the map f given by f(v)=v and f(uα)=uγ0α is an isomorphism from T(x) to T(x). Conversely, let f be an isomorphism from T(x) to T(x), so f(v)=v. Fix u=uαT(x) and suppose f(u)=uα=uγ0αT(x) for some γ0. Then for all β with x(β)=1 we have Rα1β(uα,uβ), so Rα1β(uγ0α,f(uβ)); hence f(uβ)=uγ0β. Thus x(β)=1x(γ0β)=1, so γ0x=x. Hence xT(x) witnesses J1[Γ]B1Γ. For the reverse reduction, given a rank 2 Γ-tree T, choose any non-root node v0T and define x(T)2Γ by x(T)(γ)=1vTRγ(v0,v). Then T(x(T))T, so the map Tx(T) witnesses 1ΓBJ1[Γ].

    Induction steps are similar. Given Jα[Γ]BαΓ, with a reduction f:Jα[Γ]BαΓ, we can send xXΓ to the tree T(x) with children {uγ:γΓ} of the root so that the subtree T(x)uγf(x(γ)) for each γ to show Jα+1[Γ]Bα+1Γ. The reverse reduction is handled in an analogous manner, as are limit stages. □

    Although we will see that in many instances the Γ-jump is proper on the Borel equivalence relations, we will always have that Γ is a fixed point of the Γ-jump. This is analogous to the case of tree isomorphism, which is a fixed point of the Friedman–Stanley jump.

    Proposition 4.2. For a countable group Γ, Γ is a fixed point of the Γ-jump, i.e. (Γ)[Γ]BΓ.

    Proof. Given xXΓ with each x(Γ) coding a Γ-tree Tγ, we map x to the Γ-tree T(x) with children {uγ:γΓ} of the root so that the subtree T(x)uγTγ to show (Γ)[Γ]BΓ. □

    We also note that none of the Γ are of maximal complexity among S-actions, since they are all pinned.

    Proposition 4.3. For every countable group Γ, F2BΓ, so Γ is not Borel complete.

    We will see in the following section that Γ is of maximal complexity among Aut(TΓ)-actions.

    5. Reducing Actions of Aut(TΓ) to Iterated Γ-Jumps

    In this section, we will establish that if Γ is a countable group, then every Borel equivalence relation induced by a Borel action of a closed subgroup of the automorphism group of the full Γ-tree, Aut(TΓ), is Borel reducible to some iterate Jα[Γ] of the Γ-jump.

    In the following section, we will use this, together with the fact that for certain groups Γ the power Γω has actions of cofinal essential complexity, to show that for such groups the Γ-jump is a proper jump operator. As a preview, note that by [5, Theorem 2.3.5], if H is a closed subgroup of Aut(TΓ) then every Polish H-space is reducible to a Polish Aut(TΓ)-space; similarly, we may reduce a Borel H-space to a Polish H-space. Since Γω is isomorphic to a closed subgroup of Aut(TΓ), if we know Γω has actions of cofinal essential complexity, we will be able to conclude the iterates Jα[Γ] are properly increasing in complexity.

    Recall from the previous section the full Γ-tree TΓ may be identified with Γ<ω. We let TΓk be the restriction of TΓ to branches of length k. Then Aut(TΓk) is the wreath product of k-many copies of Γ, and Aut(TΓ) is isomorphic the direct limit of the finite wreath powers of Γ.

    We are now ready to state the main theorem of this section.

    Theorem 5.1. Let Γ be a countable group and let E be a Borel equivalence relation induced by a continuous action of a closed subgroup of Aut(TΓ). Let α<ω1 be an ordinal such that E is Πα0.

    (a)

    If α=n<ω, n3, then EBJω(n2)+1[Γ].

    (b)

    If α=λ+1, λ a limit, then EBJωλ+1[Γ].

    (c)

    If α=λ+n, λ a limit, n2, then EBJω(λ+n2)+1[Γ].

    The proof of this theorem is based on some concepts and techniques from [19], and we begin by recalling the relevant portions of this work, adapted slightly to our setting. Fix a countable group Γ and a closed subgroup H of Aut(TΓ). Let E=EHX be a Πα0 orbit equivalence relation given by a continuous action of H on a Polish space X.

    The next definition concerns codes for Πα0 subsets of X×X. First, we fix for the remainder of this section an open basis {Wn} for X.

    Definition 5.1. A Πα0-code is a pair (T,u) where T is a well-founded tree of rank α so that if tT is not terminal then tnT for all n, and u:{tT:tisterminal}ω×ω. We write u=(u0,u1). For tT, define the Borel set coded below t, Rt, by

    Rt=Wu0(t)×Wu1(t),iftis terminal,nX×X\Rtn,otherwise.
    The Πα0 set coded by (T,u) is R.

    Let (T,u) be a Πα0-code for E. For tT, let |t| be the rank of t in T. For tTΓ, let ht(t) be its height in TΓ, i.e. its length as a finite sequence.

    We now define a convenient basis for H.

    Definition 5.2. Let s be an enumeration of a finite partial function from TΓ to TΓ given by s=(dis,eis):i<k, where for each i we have ht(dis)=ht(eis) equal to the length of these sequences in TΓ. We define Us={gH:i<kg(dis)=eis}.

    The collection of all such Us is a countable basis for H. Note that Us may be empty, and the same partial function will have multiple enumerations. Let B consist of all such s, and Bk consist of just those sB with maximum height of elements of the domain at most k.

    Definition 5.3. Given sB we define the type of s to be the sequence ht(dis):i<k of heights of elements of the domain of s. Let denote the set of types. For C, let kC be the size of the domain of all s of type C, diC=ht(dis) for i<kC, and jC=i<kCdiC the sum of heights of elements of the domain of s (equivalently, heights of elements of the range). For types C and D, we write CD if the sequence of heights for D extends that for C. Observe that if s,tB and UtUs, and C is the type of s, then there is a type D and t of type D with st, CD, and Ut=Ut.

    We next introduce an action of Aut(TΓ) on this basis.

    Definition 5.4. Let a(g,s)=sg be the action of Aut(TΓ) on B given by sg=(g1(dis),eis):i<k, i.e. the corresponding partial function satisfies sg=sgg1[dom(s)]. Then Usg=Usg. We use the same notation for the action of Aut(TΓk) on Bk. For s,tB we write st if s and t are in the same Aut(TΓ)-orbit (equivalently, the same Aut(TΓk)-orbit for s,tBk). If st then s and t have the same type. Note, though, that Aut(TΓ) acts on the enumerations, not the functions themselves, so two enumerations of the same partial function need not be -equivalent.

    For RX×X and U,V open subsets of H, we define the double Vaught transform

    R*U,*V={(x,y):*gU*hV(gx,hy)R}.
    The following encodings are adapted from [19], and are used to code the sections Rt*Us,*V(x)={y:(x,y)Rt*Us,*V}.

    Definition 5.5. For xX, tT with |t|1, and sB, define Nts(x) by

    Nts(x)={tn:xUs1Wu0(tn)},if|t|=1,{Ntnr(x):srBnω},if|t|>1.

    When |t|=1 this is essentially a real, and in general for |t|=α it is a hereditarily countable set of rank α. Note that t can be recovered from Nts(x). As in [19], we have the following translation property:

    Lemma 5.1. For gG, Nts(gx)=Ntsg(x).

    Definition 5.6. Let τ0 be the topology of X. For any xX and β|T| define the topology τβx as the one generated by τ0 and the sets Rt*U,*V(x) for 1|t|β and U,V{Us:sB}.

    Then each τβx is a Polish topology extending τ0. For a set BX, let BΔ={x:*g(gxB)}. We summarize the key properties of these topologies from [19, Secs. 2 and 3].

    Proposition 5.1 (Hjorth–Kechris–Louveau). Let  be an open basis for a topology on X. With the definitions above, we have

    τβx=τβgx for gH;

    The action of H on X is continuous for τβx;

    If xEy then B(xBΔyBΔ). The latter condition implies [x]E¯=[y]E¯;

    If [x]E and [y]E are Gδ then xEy iff B(xBΔyBΔ) iff [x]E¯=[y]E¯;

    If E is Πn0 for 3n<ω, then [x]E is Gδ in τn2x, so xEyiff 

    τn2x=τn2yB(τn2x)(xBΔyBΔ);

    The same holds with τ<λx in place of τn2x when E is Πλ+10 for λ a limit, and with τλ+n2x in place of τn2x when E is Πλ+n0 for λ a limit and n2.

    In case E is Π20 we have that E is reducible to Δ(), so we begin with the case where E is Πn0 for 3n<ω. We show that every Πn0 Polish H-space is reducible to some iterate of the Γ-jump of the identity relation, Jα[Γ]. We note the modifications for cases for other α later.

    Definition 5.7. Define the following hereditarily countable sets:

    A(x)={Nts(x):|t|n2sB}B(x)=m,r0,Nt0s0(x),,rk1,Ntk1sk1(x):|ti|n2ri,siBxWmi<kRti*Usi,*Uri(x)Δ.

    The idea is that A(x) codes the topology τn2x, and B(x) codes the orbit closure of x in this topology. Hjorth–Kechris–Louveau establish the following in [19, Lemma 3.2]:

    Theorem 5.2 (Hjorth–Kechris–Louveau). xEy if and only if A(x)=A(y)B(x)=B(y).

    We will show that the equality of the sets A(x) and B(x) can be encoded into iterates of the Γ-jump. We first inductively define functions cts(x) and equivalence relations FtC reducible to iterates of the Γ-jump in order to encode Nts. The bounds on the number of iterates follow from properties of the Γ-jump established earlier; we give only brief comment on the calculations in proofs in this section, and will discuss these bounds further in Sec. 7. We assume |t|1 for tT unless stated otherwise.

    Lemma 5.2. For tT with |t|1, and sBk of type C, there is a Borel function cts(x) and an equivalence relation FtC, reducible to Jω(|t|1)[Γ] for |t|>1, so that for gAut(TΓ) and r and s of type C, we have

    (a)

    If y=gx then ctsg(x)FtCcts(y);

    (b)

    If ctr(x)FtCcts(y) then Ntr(x)=Nts(y).

    Proof. (a) We use induction on |t|. For |t|=1, let cts(x)=Nts(x) and FtC=Δ(). If y=gx then ctsg(x)=Ntsg(x)=Nts(gx)=Nts(y)=cts(y), and if ctr(x)=cts(y) then Ntr(x)=Nts(y).

    For |t|>1, define FtC by

    FtC=nωD:CD(FtnD)[Γ2(jDjC)].
    Next, given CD and a sequence v=αkCβkCαkD1βkD1Γ2(jDjC) with αi,βiΓdiD for jCi<jD, we let
    cts(x)(n)(D)(v)=ctnsv(x),
    where sv=s(αkC,βkC)(αkD1,βkD1).

    If y=gx, fix nω and D with CD. Then for each vΓ2(jDjC) we have

    cts(y)(n)(D)(v)=ctnsv(gx)FtnDctn(sv)g(x)=ctnsgv(x)=ctsg(x)(n)(D)(v),
    where v=g1(αkC)βkCg1(αkD1)βkD1. Letting g̃Γ2(jDjC) be given by g̃=gdkCDiddkCDgdkD1DiddkD1D (where each concatenated factor acts on the corresponding coordinates) we have that v=g̃1v for all vΓ2(jDjC). Thus g̃ witnesses
    ctsg(x)(n)(D)(FDtn)[Γ2(jDjC)]cts(y)(n)(D),
    and hence ctsg(x)FtCcts(y).

    (b) If ctr(x)FtCcts(y) then for all nω and CD we have

    ctr(x)(n)(D)(FDtn)[Γ2(jDjC)]cts(y)(n)(D).
    Thus there is h=hn,DΓ2(jDjC) such that for all vΓ2(jDjC) we have
    ctr(x)(n)(D)(h1v)FtnDcts(y)(n)(D)(v)
    and hence
    ctnrh1v(x)FtnDctnsv(y),

    so by inductive assumption we have Ntnrh1v(x)=Ntnsv(y). Thus

    {Ntnrv(x):vΓ2(jDjC)}={Ntnsv(y):vΓ2(jDjC)},
    so
    Ntr(x)=nD:CD{Ntnrv(x):vΓ2(jDjC)}=nD:CD{Ntnsv(y):vΓ2(jDjC)}=Nts(y)
    as required.

    To see that FtC is reducible to Jω(|t|1)[Γ], note that for |t|=1 we have FtC=Δ(), and iterated jumps starting with Δ() are equivalent to those starting with Δ(2) for α>0, as noted earlier, so we may safely consider FtC to be J0[Γ] for |t|=1. Assume now that |t|>1 and the bound holds for all sT with |s|<|t|, so FtnCBJω(|t|2)[Γ]. Then

    FtC=nωD:CD(FtnD)[Γ2(jDjC)]Bkω(Jω(|t|2)[Γ])[Γk]ω.
    This is reducible to (kωJω(|t|2)+k+1[Γ])ω by Lemma 2.1, which is reducible to Jω(|t|1)[Γ] by Proposition 2.2. □

    Definition 5.8. For tT, let At(x)={Nts(x):sB}.

    Lemma 5.3. For tT, there is a Borel function ft and an equivalence relation Ft, reducible to Jω|t|[Γ], so that

    (a)

    If xEy then ft(x)Ftft(y);

    (b)

    If ft(x)Ftft(y) then At(x)=At(y).

    Proof. (a) Let Ft=C(FtC)[Γ2jC] and ft(x)(C)(v)=cts(v)(x), where s(v)=(αi,βi):i<kC for v=α0β0αkC1βkC1Γ2jC. Suppose xEy, so there is gH with y=gx. Fix C, so we have ctsg(x)FtCcts(y) for all sC from the previous lemma. Thus for each vΓ2jC we have

    ft(y)(C)(v)=cts(v)(gx)FtCct(s(v))g(x)=cts(v)(x)=ft(x)(C)(v),
    where v=g1(α0)β0g1(αkC1)βkC1. Letting g̃Γ2jC be given by g̃=gd0Cidd0CgdkC1CiddkC1C (where each concatenated factor acts on the corresponding coordinates) we have that v=g̃1v for all vΓ2jC. Thus g̃ witnesses
    ft(x)(C)(FtC)[Γ2jC]ft(y)(C),
    and hence ft(x)Ftft(y).

    (b) Suppose ft(x)Ftft(y), so for each C we have ft(x)(C)(FtC)[Γ2jC]ft(y)(C). Thus there is h=hCΓ2jC so that for all vΓ2jC we have

    ft(x)(C)(h1v)FtCft(y)(C)(v)
    and hence
    cts(h1v)(x)FtCcts(v)(y),
    so we have Nts(h1v)(x)=Nts(v)(y). Thus
    {Nts(x):sC}={Nts(y):sC},
    so
    At(x)=C{Nts(x):sC}=C{Nts(y):sC}=At(y)
    as required. □

    Lemma 5.4. There is a Borel function fA and an equivalence relation FA, reducible to Jω(n2)[Γ], so that

    (a)

    If xEy then fA(x)FAfA(y);

    (b)

    If fA(x)FAfA(y) then A(x)=A(y).

    Proof. Since t can be recovered from Nts(x) we have A(x)=A(y) if and only if At(x)=At(y) for each t. Letting FA=t:|t|n2Ft and f(x)(t)=ft(x) suffices. □

    Definition 5.9. For m,kω, r̄=(r0,,rk1)Bk and t̄=(t0,,tk1)Tk, let

    Br̄,t̄m,k(x)=Nt0s0(x),,Ntk1sk1(x):siBxWmi<kRti*Usi,*Uri(x)Δ.
    Noting that Rt*Us,*V(gx)=Rt*Usg,*V(x), we have that B(x)=B(y) if and only if for all m,k,r̄, and t̄ with |ti|n2 we have Br̄,t̄n,k(x)=Br̄,t̄n,k(y).

    Lemma 5.5. There is a Borel function fB and an equivalence relation FB, reducible to Jω(n2)[Γ], so that

    (a)

    If xEy then fB(x)FBfB(y);

    (b)

    If fB(x)FBfB(y) then B(x)=B(y).

    Proof. For m, k, r̄Bk, and t̄Tk with |ti|n2 let

    Fr̄,t̄m,k=C̄ki<kFtiCi×Δ(2)[Γ2(jC0++jCk1)],
    and for αiΓ2jCi define fr̄,t̄m,k(x) by fr̄,t̄m,k(x)(C̄)(α0αk1)=
    ct0s(α0)(x),,ctk1s(αk1)(x),1,ifx[Wmi<kRti*Usi,*Uri(x)]Δ,ct0s(α0)(x),,ctk1s(αk1)(x),0,ifnot,
    where s(αi) is as in the proof of Lemma 5.3. Similar to there, if y=gx then for each C̄ we will have g̃Γ2(jC0++jCk1) with
    fr̄,t̄m,k(x)(C̄)(g̃1(α0αk1))i<kFtiCi×Δ(2)Γ2(jC0++jCk1)fr̄,t̄m,k(y)(C̄)(α0αk1).
    Similarly, if fr̄,t̄m,k(x)Fm,kr̄,t̄fr̄,t̄m,k(y) then for each C̄ there will be g witnessing
    Nt0s0(x),,Ntk1sk1(x):siCixWmi<kRti*Usi,*Uri(x)Δ=Nt0s0(y),,Ntk1sk1(y):siCiyWmi=1kRti*Usi,*Uri(y)Δ,
    so Br̄,t̄m,k(x)=Br̄,t̄m,k(y). Finally, define FB by
    FB=mkr̄Bkt̄Tk:|ti|n2Fr̄,t̄m,k
    and fB by fB(x)(m,k,r̄,t̄)=fr̄.t̄m,k(x). □

    We are now ready to conclude the proof of Theorem 5.1.

    Proof of Theorem 5.1. Let E be Πα0.

    (a)

    For α=n3, the function f(x)=(fA(x),fB(x)) is a reduction of E to FA×FB as shown above, so EBJω(n2)[Γ]×Jω(n2)[Γ]BJω(n2)+1[Γ].

    (b)

    For α=λ+1, λ a limit, we repeat the preceding argument using the topology τ<λx in place of τn2x.

    (c)

    For α=λ+n, λ a limit and n2, we use the topology τλ+n2x.

     □

    Corollary 5.1. Let Γ be a countable group and let E be a Borel equivalence relation induced by a continuous action of Γω. Then EBJα[Γ] for some α<ω1.

    In particular, the above shows that a Π30 Polish Aut(TΓ)-space is reducible to Jω[Γ]. We can improve this slightly in the case of Σ20.

    Proposition 5.2. Let Γ be a countable group and let E be a Borel equivalence relation induced by a continuous action of a closed subgroup of Aut(TΓ). If E is Σ20 then EBnωJn[Γ].

    Proof. Since Aut(TΓ) is a closed subgroup of S, E is essentially countable by [17, Theorem 3.8], so let f be a reduction of E to E. For each x, there is some z[f(x)]E so that the set {gAut(TΓ):f(gx)=z} is nonmeager, and hence comeager in some Us. Define the relation P(x,C) on X× by

    P(x,C)sCz[f(x)]E*gUsf(gx)=z.
    Then xCP(x,C) and P is Borel and E-invariant (i.e. if P(x,C) and xEx then P(x,C)), so there is an E-invariant Borel function Ψ:X with P(x,Ψ(x)) for all x (take Ψ(x) to be the least C in some fixed enumeration of the countable set which satisfies P(x,C)). Let XC=Ψ1({C}). On XC define the reduction φ:EXCBΔ()[Γ2jC] by
    φ(x)(h)=z,if*gUs(h)f(gx)=z,*,if no suchzexists,
    where s(h) is defined as in the proof of Lemma 5.3 and * is some new element E-inequivalent to all z.

    Suppose xEy, so there is g with y=gx. Then as in the proof of Lemma 5.3 there is g̃Γ2jC so that for all hΓ2jC we have s(g̃1h)=s(h)g̃1, so that g̃ witnesses φ(x)Δ()[Γ2jC]φ(y). Conversely, if φ(x)Δ()[Γ2jC]φ(y), then there are some h, h, and z with φ(x)(h)=z* and φ(y)(h)=z. Then f(x)EzEf(y), so xEy. □

    Corollary 5.2. Let E be a countable Borel equivalence relation. If EBJα[Γ] for some α<ω1 then EBnωJn[Γ].

    Proof. Let φ be a reduction of E to Jα[Γ]. Then the Jα[Γ]-saturation B of the range of φ is Borel by the Lusin–Novikov Theorem, and EBJα[Γ]B. Thus EBJα[Γ]B is potentially Σ20 by [17, Theorem 3.8], so by [5, Theorem 5.1.5] we can refine the topology of B so that Jα[Γ]B becomes a Polish Aut(TΓ)-space which is Σ20. Thus Jα[Γ]B, and hence E, is reducible to nωJn[Γ]. □

    Note that, e.g. when Γ=𝔽2 we already have that J1[Γ]BE, since this is the shift equivalence relation E(𝔽2,2) which is bireducible with E by [11, Proposition 1.8]. Thus, the above bound is not always optimal, but we do not know if this is true for other Γ, such as Γ=. The following seems quite optimistic:

    Question 5.1. If E is a countable Borel equivalence relation reducible to some Jα[Γ], is E reducible to J2[Γ] or even to J1[Γ]?

    The same techniques will also show that isomorphism of Γ-trees is maximal among Aut(TΓ)-actions. We introduce a useful augmentation of Γ-trees.

    Definition 5.10. A labeled Γ-tree is the full Γ-tree TΓ with each node labeled with a real. We use labΓ to denote isomorphism of labeled Γ-trees.

    We may identify a labeled Γ-tree with a function from TΓ to . We can see that isomorphism of Γ-trees is bireducible with isomorphism of labeled Γ-trees.

    Lemma 5.6. labΓBΓ.

    Proof. To see that isomorphism of Γ-trees is reducible to isomorphism of labeled Γ-trees, we can identify a Γ-tree T with a subtree of TΓ, and assign the labeling where a node tTΓ is labeled ‘1’ if tT and ‘0’ if tT.

    For the reverse reduction, let g:𝒫(Γ\{1Γ}) be an injection so that for αβ we have that {1Γ}g(α) and {1Γ}g(β) are not isomorphic via a shift; such an injection exists since the shift action of Γ on 2Γ has perfectly many equivalence classes. Let f:TΓ be a labeled Γ-tree. For a node t=(α0,,αk1)TΓ, let t̃=(α0,1Γ,α1,1Γ,,1Γ,αk1). Let T(f) be the subtree of TΓ given by

    T(f)={t̃:tTΓ}{t̃1Γ:tTΓ}{t̃γ:tTΓγg(f(t))}.
    Then it is straightforward to check that the map fT(f) is a reduction from labΓ to Γ. □

    Theorem 5.3. Let G=Aut(TΓ). For any Polish G-space EGX we have EGXBΓ.

    Proof. It will suffice to show that EGXBlabΓ. Fix an enumeration {ei:iω} of TΓ, and let Cn be the type ht(e0),,ht(en1) for each n. For tTΓ with ht(t)=jCn we let stB be such that t=d0stdn1st and eist=ei for i<n. Given x, we let Tx be the labeled Γ-tree defined as follows. For t with ht(t)=jCn for some n we let Tx(t)={:xUst1W}, and let Tx(t)= for other t. We claim that the map xTx is a reduction from EGX to labΓ.

    Suppose first that gx=y. Then for t with ht(t)=jCn we have

    Ty(t)={:yUst1W}={:gxUst1W}={:xg1Ust1W}={:x(Ustg)1W}={:xUstg1W}=Tx(φ(t)),
    where φAut(TΓ) is induced by sending each node of the form d0sdn1s to g1(d0s)g1(dn1s). Then φ is an isomorphism from Ty to Tx.

    Conversely, suppose TxTy via φAut(TΓ). Let Tx be the subtree of Tx consisting of initial segments of those t with Tx(t) (equivalently, Ust), so that [Tx] is a Polish subspace of Γω. Define the set of branches Ax={α[Tx]:nsαjCn is an automorphism of TΓ}. We claim that Ax is comeager in [Tx]. To see this, note that for α[Tx] we will have that αAx exactly when each node r in TΓ appears as dis with s=sαjCn for some i<n, and for any such r any node in Tx may be extended to another node in Tx for which this is true. Now, since φ induces a homeomorphism from [Tx] to [Ty], there are αAx and βAy with φ(α)=β (i.e. φ(αn)=βn for all n). Let gα,gβAut(TΓ) be the induced automorphisms, so nUsαjCn={gα} and nUsβjCn={gβ}. Since {:xU1sαjCnW}={:yU1sβjCnW} for all n we must then have gαx=gβy. □

    The group Aut(TΓ) corresponds to the Γ-jump in an analogous way to that of the group S with respect to the Friedman–Stanley jump, so it is natural to ask if it satisfies similar properties. For instance, Friedman showed:

    Theorem 5.4 ([12, Theorem 1.5]). If E is a Borel equivalence relation reducible to some S-action, then E is reducible to Fα for some α<ω1.

    Allison has noted that the analogous result holds for Aut(TΓ)-actions:

    Corollary 5.3 (Allison). If E is a Borel equivalence relation reducible to some Aut(TΓ)-action, then E is reducible to Jα[Γ] for some α<ω1.

    Proof. Since Aut(TΓ) is a closed subgroup of S, Friedman’s theorem implies that E is reducible to some Fα, and hence to some Πα0 orbit equivalence relation of S. By [1, Theorem 2.4], E is then reducible to an action of Aut(TΓ) with a potentially Πα0 equivalence relation. By [1, Theorem 2.7], E is then reducible to a continuous action of Aut(TΓ) with a Πα0 orbit equivalence relation, and hence to some Jα[Γ] by Theorem 5.1. □

    Friedman and Stanley asked in [13] if every E given by an S-action which satisfies FαBE for all α<ω1 must be Borel complete; this remains open. We can similarly ask:

    Question 5.2. If E is given by an Aut(TΓ)-action which satisfies Jα[Γ]BE for all α<ω1, is Γ reducible to E?

    We note that there are Borel equivalence relations induced by actions of Aut(TΓ) which are not reducible to one induced by an action of Γω. This follows from the result of Allison and Panagiotopoulos that E0[] is generically ergodic with respect to any orbit equivalence relation of a TSI Polish group [2, Corollary 2.3] and the fact that Γω is TSI for every countable Γ.

    We do not know if there is a canonical obstruction to reducibility to Aut(TΓ)-actions, in the way that turbulence is an obstruction for S-actions.

    Question 5.3. Is there a dynamical characterization of when a Borel equivalence relation is reducible to an Aut(TΓ)-action?

    We close this section by noting that Shani has observed that Γ-jumps give “natural” examples of equivalence relations at intermediate levels of the Borel hierarchy, defined in [19, Sec. 6]. Namely, the -jump of F2 (which is 2 in the notation of [19]) is reducible to the relation 3,0* defined there, and has potential complexity precisely D(Π30). We do not know for which other equivalence relations and groups this holds, since the relations α,0* require pairwise-inequivalent successors at each node, and we do not know in general when E[Γ] is reducible to Ep.i.[Γ]. We will see in Proposition 7.1 that this same precise complexity is obtained for E0[2<ω].

    6. Properness of the Γ-Jump

    In this section, we consider the question of when the Γ-jump is a proper jump. To begin, we use our results of the previous section together with a result of Solecki to establish that the Γ-jump is proper for a large class of countable groups, including the -jump.

    Theorem 6.1. Let Γ be a countable group such that  or p<ω for a prime p is a quotient of a subgroup of Γ. Then the Γ-jump is a proper jump operator.

    Proof. Suppose towards a contradiction that E is a Borel equivalence relation such that Δ(2)BE and E[Γ]BE. Then by induction on α we have that Jα[Γ](E)BE for all α<ω1, successor stages following from our assumption and limit stages from Proposition 2.2 and the fact that Jλ[Γ](E)=(α<λJα[Γ](E))[Γ]B(Eω)[Γ] for a limit ordinal λ. Hence Jα[Γ]BE for all α, so by Theorem 5.1, every Borel orbit equivalence relation induced by an action of Aut(TΓ) is reducible to E. It is a theorem of Solecki [28, Theorem 1] that if Δ is one of the groups or p<ω for a prime p then Δω admits non-Borel orbit equivalence relations, and by [16] it follows that Δω and hence Aut(TΔ) induces Borel orbit equivalence relations of cofinal essential complexity. By our hypothesis and Proposition 2.4 it then follows that Aut(TΓ) induces Borel orbit equivalence relations of cofinal essential complexity, contradicting that they are all reducible to E. □

    Although the Γ-jump has no Borel fixed points for such Γ, there are always analytic equivalence relations E with E[Γ]BE. Of course, the universal analytic equivalence relation is an example. Moreover, by Proposition 4.2, the isomorphism relation Γ on countable Γ-trees is a fixed point too. Thus, we have the following corollary:

    Corollary 6.1. Let Γ be a countable group such that  or p<ω for a prime p is a quotient of a subgroup of Γ. Then Γ is not Borel.

    For such Γ, Γ gives a new example of a non-Borel, non-Borel complete isomorphism relation. Other known examples include for instance isomorphism of abelian p-groups [13], as well as several given in [29].

    Friedman and Stanley’s proof that E<BE+ utilized a theorem of Friedman’s on the non-existence of Borel diagonalizers. We do not know if an analogous result holds for Γ-jumps.

    Definition 6.1. A Borel diagonalizer for E[Γ] is a Borel E[Γ]-invariant mapping f:XΓX such that for all xXΓ and γΓ we have f(x)x(γ).

    The following is the analogue of Friedman–Stanley’s application of diagonalizers to the jump:

    Lemma 6.1. If E[Γ]BE then there is a Borel diagonalizer for (E[Γ])[Γ].

    Proof. Let f be a Borel reduction from E[Γ] to E. We may find zXΓ so that zαEzβ for all α,βΓ and f(z)zα for all α. Define F:(XΓ)ΓXΓ by

    F(x̄)(γ)=f(xγ),ifδf(xγ)xδγ,f(z),otherwise.
    Then F is (E[Γ])[Γ]-invariant, and we claim that for all x̄ and γ we have F(x̄)[Γ]xγ. Suppose instead that there is γ0 with F(x̄)E[Γ]xγ0. Let A={xα:δf(xα)xδα}{z:γδf(xγ)Exδγ}, so that ran(F(x̄))={f(y):yA}.

    If there is yA with f(xγ0)Ef(y), then xγ0E[Γ]y, so δf(xγ0)xδγ0 (noting this is true for z from its choice). Thus xγ0A, so f(xγ0)ran(F(x̄)). But F(x̄)E[Γ]xγ0, so there would be δ with f(xγ0)Exδγ0, a contradiction. Hence there is no yA with f(xγ0)Ef(y), so there is no δ with f(xγ0)Exδγ0. But then we also have xγ0A, and there is hence some δ with f(xγ0)Exδγ0, again producing a contradiction. □

    Question 6.1. Is it the case that E[Γ] doesn’t admit a Borel diagonalizer when the Γ-jump is proper? Note that this statement is at least as strong as Friedman’s theorem, since a diagonalizer for E+ easily produces a diagonalizer for E[Γ].

    We now turn to the question of finding Γ-jumps that are not proper. Recall that a group satisfies the descending chain condition if it does not have an infinite properly descending chain of subgroups. For example, the Prüfer p-groups (p) (also called quasi-cyclic groups) satisfy the descending chain condition. More generally if Γ is quasi-finite, meaning it is infinite with no infinite proper subgroups, then Γ satisfies the descending chain condition.

    We use the descending chain condition to obtain the condition that a descending chain of cosets of subgroups has nonempty intersection. One may verify that for countable groups, the descending chain condition is equivalent to this latter condition.

    Lemma 6.2. If Γ satisfies the descending chain condition, then Jλ[Γ](E) is Borel bireducible with α<λJα[Γ](E) for λ a limit and E with at least two classes.

    Proof. First, we show α<λJα[Γ](E)BJλ[Γ](E) for any infinite Γ. Let Γ={γn:nω} and λ={αn:nω}. Define f by f(x)(γn)=x(αn); then f is a reduction from α<λJα[Γ](E) to (α<λJα[Γ](E))[Γ]=Jλ[Γ](E).

    For the other direction, we define a reduction from Jλ[Γ](E)=(α<λJα[Γ](E))[Γ] to α<λ(β<αJβ[Γ](E))[Γ], which is bireducible with α<λJα[Γ](E) when E has at least two classes. Fix some a in the domain of E and let

    f(x)(α)(γ)=x(γ),ifx(γ)isinthedomainofβ<αJβ[Γ](E),a,otherwise.
    Then f is easily a homomorphism. Suppose that f(x)α<λ(β<αJβ[Γ](E))[Γ]f(x). For each α<λ let Hα={γ:γf(x)(α)(β<αJβ[Γ](E))Γf(x)(α)}, so that the Hα’s form a nonempty descending chain of cosets of subgroups of Γ. Since Γ satisfies the descending chain condition, there is some γα<λHα, and this γ satisfies γx(α<λJα[Γ](E))Γx, so xJx[Γλ](E). □

    Using Lemma 3.2, one can show that the above result also holds when Γ=, but we do not know whether it holds for other groups Γ.

    Theorem 6.2. If Γ satisfies the descending chain condition, then Jω+1[Γ]BJω[Γ]. In particular, for such Γ the Γ-jump is not a proper jump operator.

    Proof. From the previous lemma we have Jω+1[Γ]B(nωJn[Γ])[Γ] and Jω[Γ]Bnω(knJk[Γ])[Γ] so it suffices to define a Borel reduction φ from (nωJn[Γ])[Γ] to nω(knJk[Γ])[Γ]. For this we let φ(x)(n)(γ)=x(γ)n.

    To see that φ is a homomorphism, we calculate:

    xnωJn[Γ][Γ]yγαnx(γ1α)(n)Jy[Γn](α)(n)nγαknx(γ1α)(k)Jy[Γk](α)(k)nγαφ(x)(n)(γ1α)(knJk[Γ])φ(y)(n)(α)φ(x)nωknJk[Γ][Γ]φ(y).

    Now, suppose conversely that φ(x)nω(knJk[Γ])[Γ]φ(y). For each n, let

    Hn=γ:αx(γ1α)nknJk[Γ]y(α)n.
    Then the sequence Hn is a descending chain of cosets of subgroups of Γ. It follows from the descending chain condition that nHn. If γnHn, then γ witnesses that x(nωJn[Γ])[Γ]y, completing the proof. □

    We do not know if the statement of Theorem 6.2 is tight in the sense that Jω[Γ] is the least fixed-point. If Γ is a group such that the Γ-jump is improper, one may ask what is the least α such that Jα[Γ]=Jα+1[Γ]. In the following section, we will show that for all Γ we have J0[Γ]<BJ1[Γ]<BJ2[Γ].

    The following is a consequence of Theorem 6.2 together with the proofs of Theorem 6.1 and Corollary 5.1.

    Corollary 6.2. If Γ satisfies the descending chain condition, then the family of Borel orbit equivalence relations induced by continuous actions of the group Aut(TΓ) is bounded with respect to B.

    For abelian groups G, having non-Borel orbit equivalence relations is equivalent to the family of Borel orbit equivalence relations induced by continuous actions of G being unbounded with respect to B by [16, Theorem 5.11], but we do not know if this holds for Aut(TΓ). It suffices to ask about Γ:

    Question 6.2. If Γ satisfies the descending chain condition, is Γ Borel?

    From Lemma 6.1, we also have the following corollary.

    Corollary 6.3. If Γ satisfies the descending chain condition then there is a Borel diagonalizer for Jω+2[Γ].

    We conclude this section by exploring the gap between our results on proper and improper Γ-jumps. In light of Theorem 6.1, it is natural to ask for which countable groups Γ we have non-Borel orbit equivalence relations of Γω or of Aut(TΓ). For abelian groups Γ, the answer to this question is known in the case of Γω-actions. We recall the following definition from [28].

    Definition 6.2. Let Γ be a group and p a prime number. Then Γ is said to be p-compact if, for any descending chain of subgroups Gkp×Γ such that (k)π[Gk]=p, we have π[kωGk]=p. (Here π:p×Γp denotes the projection.)

    If Γ satisfies the descending chain condition, then Γ is p-compact for all primes p. Indeed, given Gk as above, for each ap let Hka={gΓ:(a,g)Gk}. Then Hka is a descending chain of cosets of subgroups of Γ, so their intersection is non-empty, meaning aπ[kωGk].

    An example of a group which is p-compact for all p, but does not satisfy the descending chain condition, is Γ=p primep. Moreover Γ is a group for which the hypotheses of both Theorems 6.1 and 6.2 are not satisfied.

    It is natural to ask whether Theorem 6.2 can be generalized to all groups which are p-compact for all p. Indeed, it is shown in [28, Theorem 2] that if Γ is p-compact for all p, then Γω does not have a non-Borel orbit equivalence relation. It is further shown in [28] that for abelian groups Γ, this is a complete characterization. The question of which non-abelian Γ admit non-Borel Γω orbit equivalence relations is open. Of course it may also be possible that some Γ-jump is proper without this condition holding.

    Question 6.3. Which countable groups Γ give rise to proper jump operators? If Γ is p-compact for all primes p, is the Γ-jump improper? Does the group p primep give rise to a proper jump operator?

    7. Bounds on Potential Complexities

    The bounds in the statement of Theorem 5.1 are not always tight, that is, sometimes it is possible to reduce an equivalence relation E to fewer iterates of the jump. As a consequence, the lower bounds on the potential complexity of Jα[Γ] that it gives are also not always tight. The bounds provided in Theorem 5.1 are derived from the definitions of the equivalence relations introduced in the proof, together with Proposition 2.2, Lemma 2.1, and the fact that α<λJα[Γ]BJλ[Γ] for limit λ (see the proof of Lemma 6.2). In general this technique requires about ω-many iterates of the Γ-jump to ensure the potential complexity has increased by one level in the Borel hierarchy.

    In this section, we provide a more direct proof that the iterated jumps have cofinal potential complexity in the special case when Γ=2<ω, and produce sharp bounds on potential complexity of the iterates of the 2<ω-jump. As a consequence we obtain an alternate proof that the 2<ω-jump is proper. Recall that for a pointclass Γ, the pointclass D(Γ) consists of all sets which are the difference of two sets in Γ, and the pointclass Ď(Γ) is its dual, consisting of the complements of all such sets.

    Proposition 7.1. For Γ=2<ω we have the following:

    Jα[2<ω]pot(D(Πα+10))\pot(Ď(Πα+10)) for α2 not a limit;

    Jλ[2<ω]pot(Σλ+10)\pot(Πλ+10) for λ a limit.

    Proof. The upper bounds follow from Corollary 3.2. To establish the lower bounds, we use the properly increasing tower Aα of equivalence relations defined by Hjorth–Kechris–Louveau in [19, §5] (where our An corresponds to their EGn+1 for finite n, and Aα to EGα for infinite α), and show that AαBJα[Γ] for each α. We will let Γ denote 2<ω throughout this proof. To define Aα, we adopt the following notation. For any x2ω we may regard x as an element of (2ω)ω, and we write xn for the nth element of 2ω in x. Also for any x2ω we let x̄(n)=1x(n).

    We let A0=Δ(2) and A1=E0. Given Aα, we define xAα+1y if and only if:

    (a)

    for all n, either xnAαyn or xn¯Aαyn, and

    (b)

    for all but finitely many n, xnAαyn.

    For a limit ordinal λ we fix an increasing sequence αnnω cofinal in λ and define xAλy if and only if:

    (a)

    for all n, either xnAαnyn or xn¯Aαnyn, and

    (b)

    for all but finitely many n, xnAαnyn.

    Hjorth–Kechris–Louveau show, in [19, Theorem 5.8] and its proof, that (with our indexing) Aαpot(Ď(Πα+10)) for α2 not a limit, and that Aλpot(Πλ+10) for λ a limit. Hence the desired lower bounds will be established once we show that each AαBJα[Γ].

    For α=0 and α=1, this is immediate. Next, suppose AαBJα[Γ]; we will show that Aα+1BJα+1[Γ]. We first claim that Aα+1B((Aα)ω)[Γ] for each α. Admitting this claim, since 2<ω2<ω×2<ω, we have (Eω)[Γ]BE[Γ] for any E by Proposition 2.5. Hence if AαBJα[Γ] then Aα+1B((Jα[Γ])ω)[Γ]B(Jα[Γ])[Γ]=Jα+1[Γ].

    To establish the claim, let x2ω be given and define αx(n,s) for nω and s2<ω by

    αx(n,s)=xn,ifs(n)=0,xn¯,ifs(n)=1.
    Then if xAα+1y, we define γΓ by γ(n)=0 if xnAαyn and γ(n)=1 otherwise. Then γ witnesses that αx is equivalent to αy. On the other hand, if αx is equivalent to αy, let γΓ witness this. Then the coordinates of γ witness that xAα+1y.

    For a limit ordinal λ, suppose AαBJα[Γ] for all α<λ; we show that AλBJλ[Γ]. A direct modification of the proof of the previous claim gives that AλB(nAαn)[Γ]. Similarly, a direct modification of the proof of Proposition 2.5 gives that (nAαn)[Γ]B(nAαn)[Γ] for Γ=2<ω. Since

    (nAαn)[Γ]B(α<λAα)[Γ]B(α<λJα[Γ])[Γ]=Jλ[Γ],
    this completes the proof. □

    We do not know the optimal complexity bounds in the case of groups other than 2<ω. In particular, we do not know precise bounds on the complexities of the iterates of the -jump.

    Question 7.1. What are the exact potential Borel complexities of the Zα’s?

    8. Generic E0-Ergodicity of Γ-Jumps

    In this section, we will show that Γ-jumps of countable Borel equivalence relations produce new examples of equivalence relations intermediate between E0ω and F2. Furthermore, we will see that although some Γ-jumps admit Borel fixed points, any such fixed point must be strictly above E0. The key notion in establishing these results is the following definition.

    Definition 8.1. We say that E is generically F-ergodic if for every Baire measurable homomorphism φ from E to F there is a y so that φ1[y]F is comeager. We say E is generically ergodic when it is generically Δ()-ergodic.

    Note that if E is generically F-ergodic, and E does not have a comeager equivalence class, then EBF. Furthermore observe that each E0[Γ]-class is meager. Also, when E is an orbit equivalence relation, the following lemma shows that we may assume φ is Borel when verifying generic F-ergodicity.

    Lemma 8.1. Let E=EGX be an orbit equivalence relation on X and F an equivalence relation on Y. If φ:XY is a Baire measurable homomorphism from E to F, then there is a Borel homomorphism φ̃ from E to F with φ̃(x)Fφ(x) for a comeager set of x.

    Proof. Let CX be a dense Gδ set so that φ is continuous on C. Let C*={x:(*g)(gxC)} be the Vaught transform, so that C* is an E-invariant dense Gδ set (see [5, Lemma 5.1.7]). Let PC*×G be given by

    P={(x,g):gxC},
    so that each section Px is comeager. By Category Uniformization (see [23, Corollary 18.7]) there is a Borel uniformization P̃P which is the graph of a Borel function s:C*G. Fix an arbitrary element y0Y; we now define φ̃ by
    φ̃(x)=φ(s(x)x)ifxC*,y0ifxC*.
    Then φ̃ is as desired. □

    Our main result will be to show that E0[Γ] is generically E-ergodic for any countable group Γ. Throughout this section we let Γ={γn:nω} be a countably infinite group and fix an increasing sequence of finite subsets Γn with Γ=nΓn.

    Definition 8.2. Let h be a Borel -action inducing E0, and let G=Γ act coordinate-wise via h to induce the orbit equivalence relation E0Γ. Then G together with the shift action of Γ on (2ω)Γ generates E0[Γ]. For each n and each k̄Γn, let Uk̄n={gG:gΓn=k̄}, so that {Uk̄n:n,k̄} is a countable basis for G.

    The following lemma is derived from [18, Theorem 7.3]:

    Lemma 8.2. Let f:E0[Γ]E be a Borel homomorphism. Then there is a Borel f̃ such that f̃(x)Ef(x) for all x, and there are E0Γ-invariant sets Xn with (2ω)Γ=nXn such that for x,xXn with xE0Γx and xΓn=xΓn we have f̃(x)=f̃(x).

    Proof. For each x, [f(x)]E={yi:iω} is countable, so there is some i so that Gi={gG:f(gx)=yi} is nonmeager, and hence comeager in some Uk̄n. Hence:

    xnk̄y[f(x)]E*gUk̄n(f(gx)=y).
    Set P(x,n)k̄y[f(x)]E*gUk̄n(f(gx)=y), so xnP(x,n). Since P is Borel and E0Γ-invariant (if P(x,n) and xE0Γx then P(x,n)), there is a E0Γ-invariant Borel function s:(2ω)Γ with P(x,s(x)) for all x. Let Xn=s1[{n}].

    For xXn, let k̄(x) be the least k̄ (in some fixed enumeration of Γn) so that y[f(x)]E*gUk̄n(f(gx)=y). Note that if xE0Γx and xΓn=xΓn then k̄(x)=k̄(x). We can now let f̃(x) be the unique y so that *gUk̄(x)n(f(gx)=y). □

    Now, Xn is nonmeager for some n, and since E0Γ is induced by a continuous group action with dense orbits it must be comeager. Let n0 be this n. Let Y0 be a comeager set with f̃ continuous on Y0. Let Y=nωγn[Y0*GXn0] so that Y is comeager and E0[Γ]-invariant.

    Lemma 8.3. For all x,xY with xΓn0=xΓn0 we have f̃(x)=f̃(x).

    Proof. Let x,xY with xΓn0=xΓn0. We can then choose gG with gx,gxY0 and gxΓn0=gxΓn0=xΓn0. Hence f̃(gx)=f̃(x) and f̃(gx)=f̃(x), so, replacing x and x by gx and gx, we may assume x,xY0.

    Suppose f̃(x)f̃(x), and let V and V be disjoint neighborhoods with f̃(x)V and f̃(x)V. We can then find neighborhoods U and U in (2ω)Γ with xU and xU, so that if yUY0 then f̃(y)V and if yUY0 then f̃(y)V. Since G-orbits are dense, the set {gG:gxUgxΓn0=xΓn0} is non-empty and open, so it contains some g with gxY0. But then f̃(gx)=f̃(x) by the previous lemma; however, then f̃(gx)V but f̃(x)V, a contradiction. □

    Lemma 8.4. For all x,xY, if there is γΓ with xγΓn0=xγΓn0 then f̃(x)Ef̃(x).

    Proof. We have γ1xΓn0=γ1xΓn0, and since Y is E0[Γ]-invariant we have f̃(γ1x)=f̃(γ1x). Since xE0[Γ]γ1x and f̃ is a homomorphism we have f̃(x)Ef̃(γ1x), and similarly for x, so the result follows. □

    Now, we are ready for the main result of this section:

    Theorem 8.1. E0[Γ] is generically E-ergodic.

    Proof. Let f:E0[Γ]E be a Borel homomorphism, and let f̃, n0, and Y be as above. By the Kuratowski–Ulam theorem we have

    *z(2ω)Γn0*w(2ω)Γ\Γn0(zwY),
    so the set
    Y={xY:*w(2ω)Γ\Γn0(xΓn0wY)}
    is comeager. It suffices to show that f̃ maps Y into a single E-class. Fix x,xY, and let γΓ so that Γn0 and γΓn0 are disjoint. We can then find w(2ω)Γ\Γn0 so that y=xΓn0wY and y=xΓn0wY. We have f̃(x)Ef̃(y) and f̃(x)Ef̃(y) by agreement on Γn0, and f̃(y)Ef̃(y) by agreement on γΓn0, so f̃(x)Ef̃(x). □

    When E is generically F-ergodic it is also generically Fω-ergodic, so we immediately get:

    Theorem 8.2. E0[Γ] is generically Eω-ergodic.

    Corollary 8.1. E0[] is generically E0ω-ergodic.

    Since (E0)ω is Borel reducible to E0[], we have in particular that (E0)ω is properly below E0[] in complexity.

    Allison and Panagiotopoulos have since strengthened the last result to show that E0[] is generically ergodic with respect to any orbit equivalence relation of a TSI Polish group [2, Corollary 2.3]. More recently, Allison has shown that an equivalence relation E is generically ergodic with respect to any orbit equivalence relation EGX with G non-Archimedean abelian if and only if E is generically E0-ergodic ([1, Theorem 6.6]), and E is generically ergodic with respect to any orbit equivalence relation EGX with G non-Archimedean TSI if and only if E is generically E-ergodic ([1, Theorem 6.5]).

    From the above, we can see that Γ-jumps do not have fixed points at the first two levels.

    Corollary 8.2. For any countable group Γ we have J0[Γ]<BJ1[Γ]<BJ2[Γ].

    Proof. For any countable Γ, J0[Γ]=Δ(2), and J1[Γ] is the shift action of Γ on 2Γ, which is countable and generically ergodic. □

    In Sec. 9, we consider which countable Borel equivalence relations are reducible to E0[], and establish in Corollary 9.2 that EBE0[], which immediately implies that EωBE0[]. We may now summarize the situation to see that E0[] and E[] are new examples of natural equivalence relations below F2 which provide genuinely new levels in the Borel complexity hierarchy.

    Theorem 8.3. We have the following :

    E0ω<BE0[]<BE[]<BF2;

    E0ω<BEω<BE[]<BF2;

    E0[] and Eω are B-incomparable.

    Previously, the only known examples of equivalence relations between Eω and F2 were the examples constructed in [30], which are non-pinned. Shani has also produced a new example of an intermediate pinned equivalence relation in [26], denoted EΠ, which is also incomparable to E0[] and E[].

    Theorem 8.4 ([26, Theorem 1.7]). EΠ is pinned and satisfies:

    Eω<BEΠ<BF2;

    EΠBE[Γ] and E0[Γ]BEΠ for any infinite countable group Γ.

    Note that these results give several other equivalence relations strictly between Eω and F2, such as Eω×E0[] and E[𝔽2] (where 𝔽2 is the free group on 2 generators). Shani has shown, as consequences of [26, Corollary 5.6 and Proposition 5.14]:

    Theorem 8.5 (Shani). The following hold:

    E[]BE0[]×Eω;

    E0[]×E0ωBE[];

    E[] and E0[]×Eω are B-incomparable;

    E[]<B(E[])2 for any generically ergodic countable Borel equivalence relation E.

    One can also ask if there are any equivalence relations strictly between E0ω and E0[].

    Question 8.1. If EBE0[], does either EBE0[] or EBE0ω?

    From the Hjorth–Kechris dichotomy for E0ω, we can obtain a weak partial result.

    Lemma 8.5. If EBE0[] then either E0ωBE or EBE.

    Proof. Let f be a reduction of E to E0[]. Set xFx iff f(x)E0f(x), so that F is of countable index below E and FBE0BE0ω. Hence either E0ωBF or FBE0. In the first case, let g be a reduction of E0ω to F, and set xEx iff g(x)Eg(x). Then EBE and E is of countable index over E0ω, so that E0ωBE (see [8, Corollary 8.32]) and hence E0ωBE. In the second case, let h be a reduction of F to E0, and define the equivalence relation E by yEy iff yE0yx,x(xExh(x)E0yh(x)E0y). Then E is a countable analytic equivalence relation with EBE, so E is essentially countable (see, e.g. [10, Proposition 7.1]); hence EBE. □

    Question 8.2. If EBE[], does either E0[]BE or EBEω?

    9. -Jumps and Scattered Linear Orders

    In this section, we give an application of our results about the -jump to the classification of countable scattered linear orders. We also consider countable Borel equivalence relations which admit an assignment of scattered linear orders to each equivalence class, and establish some complexity bounds on them. Finally, we study the classification of countable complete linear orders, and give an application to classifying more general classes of countable models.

    Definition 9.1. A linear order L is said to be scattered if there does not exist an embedding (a one-to-one order-preserving map) from to L.

    The scattered linear orders admit a derivative or collapse operation as well as a rank function. To begin, define an equivalence relation on L by xy if the interval between x,y is finite. The -equivalence classes are convex, so we may form a quotient ordering L. Next, we define equivalence relations α for any ordinal α as follows. If β has been defined, we let xβ+1y iff [x]β[y]β, where [x]β,[y]β denote the β-equivalence classes of x,y. If λ is a limit ordinal and β have been defined for all β<λ, we let xλy iff there exists β<λ such that xβy.

    Now, a linear order L is scattered if and only if there exists α such that Lα is a single point (see [23, Exercise 34.18]). Thus, we may define the rank of a scattered linear order L as the least α such that Lα is a single point. Let S denote the class of countable scattered linear orders, Sα denote the class of countable scattered linear orders of rank α, and Sα for the class of countable scattered linear orders of rank at most α.

    Proposition 9.1 ([23, Exercises 33.2, 34.18]). The set S is a Π11-complete set and the subsets Sα and Sα are Borel sets. Moreover, the function which maps a countable scattered linear order to its rank is a Π11-rank on S.

    We will write α to abbreviate Sα. Furthermore, although S is a non-Borel class of countable structures, we will write S for the isomorphism relation on all countable scattered orderings.

    Proposition 9.2. There is no absolutely Δ21 reduction from S to a Borel equivalence relation. On the other hand, no Borel complete equivalence relation is Borel reducible to S.

    Proof. For the first statement we recall from [16] (see remarks following Corollary 3.3) that there is no absolutely Δ21 reduction from Eω1 to a Borel equivalence relation, where Eω1 is the isomorphism relation on countable well-orders. Moreover, we have that Eω1 is absolutely Δ21-reducible to S (see, e.g. [9, Theorem 3.5]). Finally compositions of absolutely Δ21 reductions are again absolutely Δ21.

    For the second statement, it will follow from the results below that F2 is not reducible to S, but we can give a more basic proof. Suppose there exists a Borel reduction f from some Borel complete equivalence relation to S. Then by the Boundedness Theorem, the range of f is contained in some Sα. Since Borel complete equivalence relations are not Borel, it follows that α is not a Borel equivalence relation. But it is not difficult to see that α is Borel, for instance see Proposition 9.1. This is a contradiction. □

    The classification of scattered linear orders is closely related to the classification of -trees. We use a modification of the definition of Γ-trees given in Sec. 4, which is slightly simpler and more natural in the context of orders.

    Definition 9.2. A scattered order tree is a rooted tree together with, for each node x, a linear ordering on the set of immediate successors of x which is isomorphic to a subordering of .

    If T is a scattered order tree, we will use the < symbol for the order relation on the immediate successors of any node of T. We let SOT denote the space of scattered order trees, and SOTα the space of well-founded scattered order trees of rank α.

    Lemma 9.1. The isomorphism relation α on countable scattered linear orders of rank α is Borel bireducible with the isomorphism relation on SOT1+α.

    Proof. We first show α is Borel reducible to the isomorphism relation on SOT1+α. Given a scattered linear order L of rank α we define a scattered order tree T whose nodes consist of the β equivalence classes for βα, with the ordering tt iff tt. It is not difficult to see that LT is a Borel reduction as desired.

    To show that the isomorphism relation on SOT1+α is Borel reducible to α, we proceed by induction. For the base case, it is clear that both the isomorphism relation on SOT1 and 0 are bireducible with Δ(1).

    For the inductive step, let α>0 and assume that for all β<α there exists a Borel reduction f1+β from the isomorphism relation on SOT1+β to β. Further assume that for all β and all Tdom(fβ) we have that fβ(T) does not contain any -class of size 1. (We may do so without loss of generality, by inserting an immediate successor to each point of fβ(T).)

    Given a scattered order tree T of rank 1+α, let N denote the order type of the children of the root of T, so that N is a suborder of . For each nN let Tn denote the subtree of T rooted at the nth child of T, and let βn be the rank of Tn. Finally, let

    L=nNfβn(Tn)++1+.
    Then the mapping TL is a Borel reduction as desired. To see one can recover T from L, note that a separator widget +1+ may be identified by its -class of size 1. Thus one can determine each fβn(Tn) up to isomorphism, and then use the reductions fβn to recover each Tn and thus T up to isomorphism. □

    Note that the notion of scattered order tree carries less information than our earlier notion of -tree, since for instance there are ω many scattered order trees of rank 2 up to isomorphism, while there are continuum many (complexity E0) -trees of rank 2 up to isomorphism. However, after this level the two classifications do align in complexity, with the ranks adjusted appropriately.

    Lemma 9.2. The isomorphism relation on SOT2+α is Borel bireducible with α for α>0.

    Proof. We begin with the case when α=1. We have already shown that 1BE0. Meanwhile a scattered order tree of rank 3 may be identified with a suborder of where each node is labeled with a natural number according to the order-type of its set of children, of which there are only countably many, and hence isomorphism of SOT3 is bireducible with (Δ(ω))[]BE0.

    For α>1, given a scattered order tree S of rank 2+α, for any node of rank at least 4 we may first replace any of its children of rank at most 3 by a subset of using the α=1 case. We can then identify each remaining level with a subset of to produce a -tree of rank 1+α in an isomorphism-preserving way. Similarly, given a -tree of rank 1+α, considering each “missing” child of a non-terminal node as a trivial tree we may replace each node of rank 1 by a scattered order tree of rank 3 and order each level as a subset of to produce a scattered order tree of rank 2+α in an isomorphism-preserving way, and yielding the desired reductions. □

    We remark that it follows from this together with Proposition 9.2 that the isomorphism relation SOT on all scattered order trees is not Borel, but also not Borel complete.

    Theorem 9.1. The isomorphism relation 1+α on scattered linear orders of rank 1+α is Borel bireducible with Zα=Jα[] for α>0.

    Proof. We have 1+α is bireducible with SOT2+α by Lemma 9.1, the latter is bireducible with α by Lemma 9.2, and the latter is bireducible with Zα by Proposition 4.1. □

    It follows using Corollary 5.1 that every Borel ω-action is reducible to some α.

    It also follows using Theorem 6.1 that the complexity of the classification of countable scattered linear orders increases strictly with the rank. For comparison, we note that Alvir and Rossegger have shown in [4] that the complexity of Scott sentences of scattered linear orders also increases strictly with the rank.

    We now turn to the relationship between isomorphism of scattered linear orders and assignments of scattered linear orderings to equivalence classes of countable Borel equivalence relations. We recall the following notion from [22].

    Definition 9.3. Let E be a countable Borel equivalence relation on X, and let 𝒦 be a class of -structures. We say that E admits a Borel assignment of structures in 𝒦 to each equivalence class if there is an assignment C𝒜C assigning a structure in 𝒦 with universe C to each E-equivalence class C, so that for each k-ary R the relation

    R̃(x,y1,,yk)y1,,yk[x]ER𝒜[x]E(y1,,yk)
    is Borel.

    A more general study of structurable equivalence relations may be found in [7]. Kechris has shown in [22] that every countable Borel equivalence relation which admits a Borel assignment of scattered linear orders to each equivalence class is amenable, and has asked whether the converse is true. It is also a long-standing open question whether every countable amenable Borel equivalence relation is hyperfinite. We give here a partial characterization of when a countable Borel equivalence relation admits a Borel assignment of scattered linear orders to each equivalence class.

    Lemma 9.3. If a countable Borel equivalence relation E admits a Borel assignment of scattered linear orders of rank 1+α to each equivalence class, then EBZ1+α.

    Proof. For α=0, [11, Theorem 5.1] gives that E admits an assignment of orders of rank 1 if and only if E is hyperfinite, and hence reducible to E0BZ1. For α>0, suppose E is a countable Borel equivalence relation on X which admits a Borel assignment of scattered linear orders of rank 1+α to each equivalence class. From Theorem 9.1, it will suffice to show that EB2+α. Given xX, let <[x]E be the order assigned to [x]E, and let [x]E be the finite-interval relation with respect to <[x]E. Let xy iff xEy and x[x]Ey, so that is a subequivalence relation of E and <[x]E induces a scattered linear order of rank 1 on [x]. Hence, we may fix a reduction f from to 2. We now assign a scattered linear order to each xX as follows. We start with the -equivalence classes in [x]E, so that <[x]E induces a scattered order of rank α on these classes. For each y[x]E we then replace [y] by the ordering of rank 2 given by f(y) to produce an ordering of rank 2+α. Since [x] will be encoded in this ordering via f, this gives the desired reduction from E to 2+α. □

    Lemma 9.4. Let E be a countable Borel equivalence relation. Then EBE0[] if and only if E is *-orderable, i.e. E admits a Borel assignment of suborders of * to each equivalence class.

    Proof. Suppose first that E is a countable Borel equivalence relation with EBE0[]. By Lemma 3.3 we have (E0)[]B(E0)p.i.[], so let f be a reduction of E to (E0)p.i.[]. Recall that E0 denotes the product of -many copies of E0, so E0 is a countable index subequivalence relation of E0[] and E0E0ω. Because of pairwise inequivalence, on the range of f there is a Borel ordering of E0-classes with the property that the E0-classes within each E0[]-class are isomorphic to the ordering .

    Let be the pullback of E0 under f, that is, xx iff f(x)E0f(x). Then is a subequivalence relation of E, and hence countable. Since BE0ω, it follows from the Sixth Dichotomy Theorem (see Hjorth–Kechris, Theorem 7.1) that is hyperfinite. Hence there is AN assignment of suborders of to each -class. Moreover, letting 0 be the pullback of , we have that the -classes within each E-class are isomorphic to a suborder of . It follows that there is a Borel assignment of suborders of * to the equivalence classes of E.

    The converse follows from the previous lemma. □

    Note that this is analogous to [11, Theorem 5.1] which gives that a countable Borel equivalence relation is reducible to E0 if and only if it admits a Borel assignment of suborders of to each equivalence class. We do not know whether analogous results for the forward direction hold for higher iterates of the -jump.

    Question 9.1. For a countable Borel equivalence relation E, does E admit an assignment of scattered linear orders of rank 1+α iff EBJα[]?

    As observed in Corollary 5.2, if E is a countable Borel equivalence relation with EBJα[] for some α<ω1, then EBnωJn[]. In light of Lemma 9.3, Corollary 5.2, and boundedness, we have the following corollary.

    Corollary 9.1. If E is a countable Borel equivalence relation which admits a Borel assignment of scattered linear orders to each equivalence class, then EBω.

    We may then ask:

    Question 9.2. If E is a countable Borel equivalence relation with EBω, is E hyperfinite?

    Here it may be worth investigating a restricted form of the Γ-jump using finitely-supported wreath products to preserve countability of the equivalence relations, instead of the full wreath product used in the Γ-jump.

    Using the above results, we can now establish the following corollary:

    Corollary 9.2. EBE0[].

    Proof. Suppose towards a contradiction that EBE0[]. From Lemma 9.4, there would be a Borel assignment of suborders of * to the equivalence classes of E, and therefore by [22] we would have that E was amenable. Since E is not amenable, this contradiction completes the proof. □

    Next, we consider a class of linear orders that is very closely related to the scattered linear orders, and show that this together with our results above leads to a model-theoretic corollary.

    Definition 9.4. A linear order L is said to be complete if for every AL, if A has an upper bound then A has a least upper bound.

    Every countable complete linear order is scattered. Indeed, if L is countable and complete then it has just countably many Dedekind cuts. It follows that there is no embedding of into L, and that L is scattered. On the other hand, one may verify that if L is a countable scattered linear order then its Dedekind completion L̄ is a countable complete linear order. In the following, we let C denote the subset of S consisting of the countable complete linear orders.

    Theorem 9.2. The statements of Lemma 9.1holds with α replaced with αC. In particular for all α we have that the relations Zα, 1+α, and 1+αC are Borel bireducible with one another.

    Proof. In the proof of Lemma 9.1, given a sequence fβn(Tn) we defined a scattered order L using the separator +1+. Assuming the fβn(Tn) are complete, we can ensure that L will be complete by using the separator 1++1++1. □

    We close this section by mentioning an application to the classification of countable models of certain theories T, which was pointed out to us by Ali Enayat. Let T be a theory with built-in Skolem functions, and with a unary predicate P and a linear ordering < of P. Further suppose that there is a model M of T with a proper elementary end extension N, that is, N is an elementary extension of M and PM<PN\PM. We refer the reader to [27] for further context.

    It follows directly from [27, Theorems 1.2 and 2.1(2)] that if T is as above, then for any α there is a Borel reduction from αC to the isomorphism relation on countable models of T. In particular we have the following remark:

    Remark 9.1. If T is as above, then for any α there is a Borel reduction from Zα to the isomorphism relation on countable models of T.

    Acknowledgments

    We would like to thank Shaun Allison, Ali Enayat, Aristoteles Panagiotopoulos, and Assaf Shani for helpful discussions about the content of this paper. We would also like to thank the referee for several helpful suggestions, in particular for pointing out that our original complexity bounds in Proposition 7.1 were not correct.

    References

    • 1. S. Allison, Non-Archimedean TSI Polish groups and their potential Borel complexity spectrum, preprint (2020), arXiv:2010.05085. Google Scholar
    • 2. S. Allison and A. Panagiotopoulos , Dynamical obstructions to classification by (co)homology and other TSI-group invariants, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 374(12) (2021) 8793–8811. Crossref, Web of ScienceGoogle Scholar
    • 3. S. Allison and A. Shani, Actions of tame abelian product groups, preprint (2021), arXiv:2105.05144. Google Scholar
    • 4. R. Alvir and D. Rossegger , The complexity of Scott sentences of scattered linear orders, J. Symb. Log. 85(3) (2020) 1079–1101. Crossref, Web of ScienceGoogle Scholar
    • 5. H. Becker and A. S. Kechris , The Descriptive Set Theory of Polish Group Actions, London Mathematical Society Lecture Note Series, Vol. 232 (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1996). CrossrefGoogle Scholar
    • 6. R. Camerlo, A. Marcone and L. M. Ros , On isometry and isometric embeddability between ultrametric Polish spaces, Adv. Math. 329 (2018) 1231–1284. Crossref, Web of ScienceGoogle Scholar
    • 7. R. Chen and A. S. Kechris , Structurable equivalence relations, Fund. Math. 242(2) (2018) 109–185. Crossref, Web of ScienceGoogle Scholar
    • 8. J. D. Clemens , Relative primeness and Borel partition properties for equivalence relations, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 375(1) (2022) 111–149. Crossref, Web of ScienceGoogle Scholar
    • 9. J. Clemens, S. Coskey and S. Potter , On the classification of vertex-transitive structures. Arch. Math. Log. 58(5–6) (2019) 565–574. Crossref, Web of ScienceGoogle Scholar
    • 10. J. D. Clemens, D. Lecomte and B. D. Miller , Essential countability of treeable equivalence relations, Adv. Math. 265 (2014) 1–31. Crossref, Web of ScienceGoogle Scholar
    • 11. R. Dougherty, S. Jackson and A. S. Kechris , The structure of hyperfinite Borel equivalence relations, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 341(1) (1994) 193–225. Crossref, Web of ScienceGoogle Scholar
    • 12. H. M. Friedman , Borel and Baire reducibility, Fund. Math. 164(1) (2000) 61–69. Crossref, Web of ScienceGoogle Scholar
    • 13. H. Friedman and L. Stanley , A Borel reducibility theory for classes of countable structures, J. Symb. Log. 54(3) (1989) 894–914. Crossref, Web of ScienceGoogle Scholar
    • 14. S. Gao , Invariant Descriptive Set Theory, Pure and Applied Mathematics, Vol. 293 (CRC Press, Boca Raton, FL, 2009). Google Scholar
    • 15. L. A. Harrington, A. S. Kechris and A. Louveau , A Glimm–Effros dichotomy for Borel equivalence relations, J. Amer. Math. Soc. 3(4) (1990) 903–928. CrossrefGoogle Scholar
    • 16. G. Hjorth , An absoluteness principle for Borel sets, J. Symb. Log. 63(2) (1998) 663–693. Crossref, Web of ScienceGoogle Scholar
    • 17. G. Hjorth and A. S. Kechris , Borel equivalence relations and classifications of countable models, Ann. Pure Appl. Log. 82(3) (1996) 221–272. Crossref, Web of ScienceGoogle Scholar
    • 18. G. Hjorth and A. S. Kechris , Recent developments in the theory of Borel reducibility, Fund. Math. 170(1–2) (2001) 21–52. Dedicated to the memory of Jerzy Łoś. Crossref, Web of ScienceGoogle Scholar
    • 19. G. Hjorth, A. S. Kechris and A. Louveau , Borel equivalence relations induced by actions of the symmetric group, Ann. Pure Appl. Log. 92(1) (1998) 63–112. Crossref, Web of ScienceGoogle Scholar
    • 20. S. Jackson, A. S. Kechris and A. Louveau , Countable Borel equivalence relations, J. Math. Log. 2(1) (2002) 1–80. LinkGoogle Scholar
    • 21. V. Kanovei , Borel Equivalence Relations: Structure and Classification, University Lecture Series, Vol. 44 (American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI, 2008). CrossrefGoogle Scholar
    • 22. A. S. Kechris , Amenable equivalence relations and Turing degrees, J. Symb. Log. 56(1) (1991) 182–194. Crossref, Web of ScienceGoogle Scholar
    • 23. A. S. Kechris , Classical Descriptive Set Theory, Graduate Texts in Mathematics, Vol. 156 (Springer-Verlag, New York, 1995). CrossrefGoogle Scholar
    • 24. A. Louveau , On the reducibility order between Borel equivalence relations, in Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science IX, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, Vol. 134 (North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1994), pp. 151–155. Google Scholar
    • 25. C. Rosendal , Cofinal families of Borel equivalence relations and quasiorders, J. Symb. Log. 70(4) (2005) 1325–1340. Crossref, Web of ScienceGoogle Scholar
    • 26. A. Shani, Strong ergodicity around countable products of countable equivalence relations, preprint (2019), arXiv:1910.08188. Google Scholar
    • 27. S. Shelah , End extensions and numbers of countable models, J. Symb. Log. 43(3) (1978) 550–562. Crossref, Web of ScienceGoogle Scholar
    • 28. S. Solecki , Equivalence relations induced by actions of Polish groups, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 347(12) (1995) 4765–4777. Crossref, Web of ScienceGoogle Scholar
    • 29. D. Ulrich, R. Rast and M. C. Laskowski , Borel complexity and potential canonical Scott sentences, Fund. Math. 239(2) (2017) 101–147. Crossref, Web of ScienceGoogle Scholar
    • 30. J. Zapletal , Pinned equivalence relations, Math. Res. Lett. 18(3) (2011) 559–564. Crossref, Web of ScienceGoogle Scholar